Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourseof the Human
Sciences
Jacques Derrida
Perhaps something has occurred in the history of the concept of
structure that could be called an "event", if this loaded word did
not entail a meaning which it is precisely the function of
structural--or structuralist--thought to reduce or to suspect. Let
us speak of an "event" nevertheless, and let us use quotation marks
to serve as a precaution. What would this event be then? Its
exterior form would be that of a rupture and a redoubling.
It would be easy enough to show that the concept of structure and
even the word "structure" itself are as old as the episteme--that
is to say, as old as Western science and Western philosophy--and
that their roots thrust deep into the soil of ordinary language,
into whose deepest recesses the episteme plunges in order to gather
them up and to make them part of itself in a metaphorical
displacement. Nevertheless, up to the event which I wish to mark
out and define, structure--or rather the structurality of
structure--although it has always been at work, has always been
neutralized or reduced, and this by a process of giving it a center
or of referring it to a point of presence, a fixed origin. The
function of this center was not only to orient, balance, and
organize the structure--one cannot in fact conceive of an
unorganized structure—but above all to make sure that the
organizing principle of the structure would limit what we might
call the play of the structure. By orienting and organizing the
coherence of the system, the centre of a structure permits the play
of its elements inside the total form. And even today the notion of
a structure lacking any center represents the unthinkable
itself.
Nevertheless, the center also closes off the play which it opens up
and makes possible. As center, it is the point at which the
substitution of contents, elements, or terms is no longer possible.
At the center, the permutation or the transformation of elements
(which may of course be structures enclosed within a structure) is
forbidden. At least this permutation has always remained
interdicted (and I am using this word deliberately). Thus it has
always been thought that the center, which is by definition unique,
constituted that very thing within a structure which while
governing the structure, escapes structurality. This is why
classical thought concerning structure could say that the center
is, paradoxically, within the structure and outside it. The center
is at the center of the totality, and yet, since the center does
not belong to the totality (is not part of the totality), the
totality has its center elsewhere. The center is not the center.
The concept of centered structure-although it represents coherence
itself, the condition of the episteme as philosophy or science--is
contradictorily coherent. And as always, coherence in contradiction
expresses the force of a desire. The concept of centered structure
is in fact the concept of a play based on a fundamental ground, a
play constituted on the basis of a fundamental immobility and a
reassuring certitude, which itself is beyond the reach of play. And
on the basis of this certitude anxiety can be mastered, for anxiety
is invariably the result of a certain mode of being implicated in
the game, of being caught by the game, of being as it were at stake
in the game from the outset, And again on the basis of what we call
the center (and which, because it can be either inside or outside,
can also indifferently be called the origin or end, arche or
telos), repetitions, substitutions,transformations, and
permutations are always taken from a history of meaning
[sens]--that is, in a word, a history—whose origin may always be
reawakened or whose end may always be anticipated in the form of
presence. This is why one perhaps could say that the movement of
any archaeology, like that of any eschatology, is an accomplice of
this reduction of the structurality of structure and always
attempts to conceive of structure on the basis of a full presence
which is beyond play.
If this is so, the entire history of the concept of structure,
before the rupture of which we are speaking, must
be thought of as a series of substitutions of center for center, as
a linked chain of determinations of the center.
Successively, and in a regulated fashion, the center
receives different forms or names. The history of
metaphysics, like the history of the West, is the history of these
metaphors and metonymies. Its matrix--if you will pardon me for
demonstrating so little and for being so elliptical in order to
come more quickly to my principal theme--is the determination of
Being as presence in all senses of this word. It could be shown
that all the names related to fundamentals, to principles, or to
the center have always designated an invariable presence--eidos,
arch,telos, energeia,
ousia ( essence,
existence, substance, subject )
aletheia, transcendentality, consciousness, God, man, and so
forth.
The event I called a rupture, the disruption I alluded to at the
beginning of this paper, presumably would have come about when the
structurality of structure had to begin to be thought, that is to
say, repeated, and this is why I said that this disruption was
repetition in every sense of the word. Henceforth, it became
necessary to think both the law which somehow governed the desire
for a center in the constitution of structure, and the process of
signification which orders the displacements and substitutions for
this law of central presence--but a central presence which has
never been itself, has always already been exiled from itself into
its own substitute. The substitute does not substitute itself for
anything which has somehow existed before it. Henceforth, it was
necessary to begin thinking that there was no center, that the
center could not be thought in the form of a present being, that
the center had no natural site, that it was not a fixed locus but a
function, a sort of nonlocus in which an infinite number of sign
substitutions
came into play. This was the moment when language invaded the
universal problematic, the moment when, in the absence of a center
or origin, everything became discourse--provided we can agree on
this word--that is to say, a system in which the central signified,
the original or transcendental signified, is never absolutely
present outside a system of differences. The absence of the
transcendental signified extends the domain and the play of
signification infinitely.
Where and how does this decentering, this thinking the
structurality of structure, occur? It would be somewhat naive to
refer to an event, a doctrine, or an author in order to designate
this occurrence. It is no doubt part of the totality of an era, our
own, but still it has always already begun to proclaim itself and
begun to work. Nevertheless, if we wished to choose several
"names", as indications only, and to recall those authors in whose
discourse this occurrence has kept most closely to its most radical
formulation, we doubtless would have to cite the Nietzschean
critique of metaphysics, the critique of the concepts of Being and
truth, for which were substituted the concepts of play,
interpretation, and sign (sign without present truth); the Freudian
critique of self-presence, that is, the critique of consciousness,
of the subject, of self-identity and of self-proximity or
self-possession; and, more radically, the Heideggerean destruction
of metaphysics, of onto-theology, of the determination of Being as
presence. But all these destructive discourses and all their
analogues are trapped in a kind of circle. This circle is unique.
It describes the form of the relation between the history of
metaphysics and the destruction of the history of metaphysics.
There is no sense in doing without the concepts of metaphysics in
order to shake metaphysics. We have no language--no syntax and no
lexicon--which is foreign to this history; we can pronounce not a
single destructive proposition which has not already had to slip
into the form, the logic, and the implicit postulations of
precisely what it seeks to contest. To take one example from many:
the metaphysics of presence is shaken with the help of the concept
of sign. But, as I suggest a moment ago, as soon as one seeks to
demonstrate in this way that there is no transcendental or
privileged signified and that the domain or play of signification
henceforth has no limit, one must reject even the concept and word
"sign" itself--which is precisely what cannot be done. For the
signification "sign" has always been understood and determined, in
its meaning, as sign-of, a signifier referring to a signified, a
signifier different from its signified. If one erases the radical
difference between signifier and signified, it is the word
"signifier" itself which must be abandoned as a metaphysical
concept. When Levi-Strauss says in the preface to The Raw and the
Cooked that he has "sought to transcend the opposition between the
sensible and the intelligible by operating from the outset at the
level of signs", the necessity, force, and legitimacy of his act
cannot make us forget that the concept of the sign cannot in itself
surpass this opposition between the sensible and theintelligible.
The concept of the sign, in each of its aspects, has been
determined by this opposition throughout the totality of its
history. It has lived only on this opposition and its system. But
we cannot do without the concept of the sign, for we cannot give up
this metaphysical complicity without also giving up the critique we
are directing against this complicity, or without the risk of
erasing difference in the self-identity of a signified reducing its
signifier into itself or, amounting to the same thing, simply
expelling its signifier outside itself. For there are two
heterogenous ways of erasing the difference between the signifier
and the signified: one, the classic way, consists in reducing or
deriving the signifier, that is to say, ultimately in submitting
the sign to thought; the other, the one we are using here against
the first one, consists in putting into question the system in
which the preceding reduction functioned: first and foremost, the
opposition between the sensible and the intelligible. For the
paradox is that the metaphysical reduction of the sign needed the
opposition it was reducing. The opposition is systematic with the
reduction. And what we are saying here about the sign can be
extended to all the concepts and all the sentences of metaphysics,
in particular to the discourse on "structure". But there are
several ways of being caught in this circle. They are all more or
less naive, more or less empirical, more or less systematic, more
or less close to the formulation--that is, to the formalization--of
this circle. It is these differences which explain the multiplicity
of destructive discourses and the disagreement between those who
elaborate them. Nietzsche, Freud, and Heidegger, for example,
worked within the inherited concepts of metaphysics. Since these
concepts are not elements or atoms, and since they are taken from a
syntax and a system, every particular borrowing brings along with
it the whole of metaphysics. This is what allows these destroyers
to destroy each other reciprocally---for example, Heidegger
regarding Nietzsche, with as much lucidity and rigor as bad faith
and misconstruction, as the last metaphysician, the last
"Platonist". One could do the same for Heidegger himself, for
Freud, or for a number of others. And today no exercise is more
widespread.
What is the relevance of this formal schema when we turn to what
are called the "human sciences"? One of them perhaps occupies a
privileged place--ethnology. In fact one can assume that ethnology
could have been born as a science only at the moment when a
decentering had come about: at the moment when European
culture--and, in consequence, the history of metaphysics and of its
concepts--has been dislocated, driven from its locus, and forced to
stop considering itself as the culture of reference. This moment is
not first and foremost a moment of philosophical or scientific
discourse. It is also a moment which is political, economic,
technical, and so forth. One can say with total security that there
is nothing fortuitous about the fact that the critique of
ethnocentrism--the very condition for ethnology--should be
systematically and historically contemporaneous with the
destruction of the history of metaphysics. Both belong to one and
the same era. Now, ethnology-like any science--comes about within
the element of discourse. And it is primarily a European science
employing traditional concepts, however much it may struggle
against them. Consequently, whether he wants to or not--and this
does not depend on a decision on his part--the ethnologist accepts
into his discourse the premises of ethnocentrism at the very moment
when he denounces them. This necessity is irreducible; it is not a
historical contingency. We ought to consider all its implications
very carefully. Bur if no one can escape this necessity, and if no
one is therefore responsible for giving into it, however little he
may do so, this does not mean that all the ways of giving in to it
are of equal pertinence. The quality and fecundity of a discourse
are perhaps measured by the critical rigor with which this relation
to the history of metaphysics and to inherited concepts is
thought. Here is a question both of a critical
relation to the language of the social sciences and a critical
responsibility of the discourse itself. It is a question of
explicitly and systematically posing the problem of the status of a
discourse which borrows from a heritage the resources necessary for
the deconstruction of that heritage itself. A problem of economy
and strategy.
加载中,请稍候......