Of Philosophical Study in the
20th Century
As
an old subject, like many other subjects, the study of philosophy
is still continuously expanding and deepening in the
20th century, and in this process, it
evolves some new branches (such as logical positivism, philosophy
of science, existentialism, etc), and also spawns many important
new ideas, which all show that the 20th-century
philosophy is still full of vitality and energy, and modern
philosophy also becomes a wide-ranging field; but, these many-sided
new developments also result in certain chaos of philosophy, and
thus, it will be a quite meaningful thing to do some systematic and
deep combing and discussions about 20th-century
philosophical study. In this paper, we prepare to do some
investigations about the academic thought and general
characteristic of 20th-century philosophy, and
meanwhile, we will also incorporate some new views of our
own.
(I) Some
Branches of 20th-Century Philosophy
Compared with
the 18th and
19th centuries, there are certainly
more philosophical branches in the 20thcentury, and as
is well known, the philosophical branches in the
18th and
19th centuries are somewhat few, and no
matter for German philosophy, English philosophy, French philosophy
or American philosophy, it is all so, while the
20th-century philosophy has a large number of branches
and scholars; therefore, in this part, we firstly prepare to do
some analyses, arrangements and discussions about these
philosophical branches.
1 Frege, Whitehead and Russell’s logical
study. The
development of modern logic is a long and somewhat complex process,
and many scholars make important contributions, among them, as one
of the founders of mathematical logic, Frege does brilliant
contributions. One basic characteristic of Frege’s study is to use
logical symbols to quantitatively study many logical problems,
which is quite different from the literary study of many scholars;
to better understand the research characteristic of Frege, we want
to discuss one specific problem, namely, the “universality”
problem.
We firstly
give a judgment:
| α Ф(α)
It means the following judgment: no matter
what the variable is, the function is always a fact.
The horizontal line
left to the concavity is content line, and it means that no matter
what value α is, Ф(α) is
always valid; the horizontal line right to the concavity is the
content line
of Ф(α), and here we must substitute definite things
at α.
Through|
α X(α)
denies: no matter what
value α is, X(α) is
always valid. But this does not deny: we can
give α a
value such
that X() is a fact.
| A
α X(α)
means that the
situation we
confirm α X(α) and
deny A does not exist, but it absolutely does not deny the
situation in which we
affirm X() but deny A: because as we see in the above, we can
affirm X() but
deny α X(α). Thereby,
here we cannot substitute any value at α,
and also does not harm the validity of this
judgment. It illustrates that why the concavity with German letter
is necessary: it limits the range of universality this letter
represents.
A Latin letter can use the content of the
whole judgment as its range, and then it does not need the
concavity of content line.
A Latin letter can always substitute a
German letter which does not exist in a judgment, and here the
concavity should follow the judgment bar. For example, we can
use
| α X(α)
To replace
| X(a),
If α merely exists in the variable
of X(α).
Similarly, it is obvious that, if A is a function, and a
does not appear, and if a is just in the variable
of Ф(a), then from
| Ф(a)
A
We can deduce
| α Ф(α)
A
If we
deny α X(α), then
it is necessary to give a one value which
denies Ф(a). Thus, if we
deny α X(α) and
affirm A, then it is necessary to
give αone value which
will affirm A and deny Ф(α).
But
for
| Ф(a)
A
We cannot do this:
because it means, no matter what a is, we all exclude the situation
denying Ф(a) and affirming A.
Now we
investigate several symbol combinations
| α X(α)
It means people can
find something, for
example, , which can
deny X(). Thereby, it can be translated into: “There are some
things, and they do not have property X.”
| α X(α)
Its meaning is different, and it
means: “no matter
what α is, we
can always deny X(α)”, or “there are no things which have property
X”; or we call the
thing which have property X as X, then it means “there are no
X”.
| α P(α)
X(α)
Means: “no matter what is
at α, there are no situation
denying P(α) and
affirming X(α)”.Thus
here the following situation is possible, for some values
of α, they can
affirm P(α) and
affirm X(α), for some other values,
affirming P(α) and
denying X(α), and for some other values,
denying P(α) and denying X(α), and it can be translated as: “If one thing have property
X, then it also has property
P”, or “every X is
P”, or “all X are
P”.
It is
exactly the way to express causal links.
| α P(α)
ψ(α)
means: “ We can not
give such α, which affirm both P(α) andψ(α).” Which can
be translated as: “For things which have
property ψ, they do
not have property P”, or “no ψ is P”.[1]
From
these quotations, we can easily see, Frege’s logical research has a
strong mathematical characteristic, and they are all expressed
through logical symbols, and these research are also somewhat
systematic and deep, which all have far-reaching impacts on the
subsequent research of mathematical logic.
Whitehead
also makes somewhat large contribution in logic; firstly, by
carefully reading his books, we can know, he has a good logic
foundation and can do many complex and difficult symbolic proofs,
and meanwhile, he is also mainly responsible for the mathematical
part of Principia
Mathematica. About Principia
Mathematica this classic logical work, since
it is very long, and thus, we think, scholars who can truly finish
reading it and understand it are actually very few; for example,
though Quine and Carnap also often discuss
about Principia
Mathematica, they probably just understand
part of it, while only few scholars like Godel truly understand
this book. Meanwhile, as for Whitehead’s philosophical research,
his academic and thoughtful quality is not sufficient, for example,
he is not very familiar with many basic problems in philosophy,
such as thinking and being, language reference, the relationship
between experience and reason, etc, and the philosophical problems
he deals with are probably some marginal and unimportant problems.
To conclude, Whitehead’s logical and philosophical research is
somewhat broad, and also has certain value.
Russell
also makes certain contribution in logic, such as the description
theory; to know the basic characteristic of his logical study,
below, we want to quote his one passage: “Let us assume that we
know the five formal principles of deduction enumerated
in Principia
Mathematica. (M. Nicod has reduced these to
one, but as it is a complicated proposition, we will begin with the
five.) These five propositions are as follows:-
(1) ‘p
or p’ implies p-i.e. if either p is
true or p is true, then p is true.
(2) q
implies ‘p or q’-i.e. the disjunction ‘p or
q’ is true when one of its alternatives is
true.
(3) ‘p
or q’ implies ‘q or p’. This would not be
required if we had a theoretically
more perfect notation, since in the conception
or disjunction there is no order involved, so that ‘p or q’ and ‘q
or p’ should be identical. But since our symbols, in any convenient
form, inevitably introduce an order, we need suitable assumptions
for showing that the order is irrelevant.
(4) If
either p is true or ‘q or r’ is true, then
either q is true or ‘p or r’ is true. (The twist in this
proposition serves to increase its deductive power.)
(5) If
q implies r, then ‘p or q’ implies ‘p or
r’.”[2]
In this
passage, Russell mainly discusses about some basic types of
deductive method, and from it, we can see, he can make certain
symbolic deductions, and his expositions are also somewhat
systematic. On the other hand, through reading Russell’s
mathematical works, we can also see, Russell’s logic foundation is
not very deep, and he can do certain symbolic reasoning, but can
not do some complex and deep symbolic computations and proofs,
which is also a fact we need to know. To conclude, about Russell’s
logical study, we need to dialectically view.
2 Quine, Carnap and Ayer’s logical
philosophy and language philosophy. As is well known,
logical philosophy and language philosophy form a large area of
20th-century philosophy, and there are also many
important scholars (like Austin, etc), here, we just want to
discuss about Quine, Carnap and Ayer these three representative
figures’ relevant academic
research. Generally speaking, the range of
Quine’s logical philosophy and language philosophy is broad, and
quite systematic and deep, and also has good originality. About his
language research, we want to firstly quote his one passage: “I
have argued that we can use singular terms significantly in
sentences without presupposing that there are the entities which
those terms purport to name. I have argued further that we can use
general terms, for example, predicates, without conceding them to
be names of abstract entities. I have argued further that we can
view utterances as significant, and as synonymous or heteronymous
with one another, without countenancing a realm of entities called
meanings.”[3] In this
paragraph, Quine thinks the logic of language is decided by the
essence which language expresses, and has little to do with the
formal usage it adopts; from this paragraph, we can see, Quine’s
language and logic research are infiltrated together, and he uses
the mindset of logic to examine language problem, which is an
important characteristic of Quine’s research. About his logical
research, the following paragraph is representative: “The operator
may be read ‘the class of all objects x such that’. The class ---is
definable, by description, as the class y to which any object x
will belong if and only if ---; symbolically, .(β)(α)((α∈β)≡Φ).
Further the class {x} whose sole member is x, and the class {x, y}
whose sole members are x and y, are definable thus: {α} for β (β=α)
{α, β} for γ (γ=α) ∨(γ=β).”[4] Here, Quine
defines a new logical symbol-class, and he uses strict logical
symbol to define this operation, and from it, we can know, Quine’s
logical research is conducted through symbolic reasoning, and
meanwhile, his these logical research also has quite originality,
and has definite thoughtful substance. To sum up, Quine’s logical
philosophy and language philosophy have high originality, and are
also somewhat systematic and rich, thus, also deserve our deep
reading and study.
The quality
of Carnap’s logical philosophy and philosophy of science is also
high, and the range of problems he discusses is also extensive,
systematic and profound, which involves many aspects such as logic,
epistemology, philosophy of science, semantics, etc, and also has
certain originality; to better know his logical foundation, we want
to firstly quote his one passage with symbolic contents:
“
a. +(1)
pÉp∨q.
(2)
qÉ p∨q.
(3)
qÉ(pÉq).
(4)
~pÉ( pÉq).
b. +(1)
p.qÉp.
(2)
p.qÉq.
+c.
d. +(1)
(p∨q). ~pÉq.
+(2) (p∨q). ~qÉp.
+(3) (pÉq). pÉq.
(4)
pÉ[(pÉq) Éq].
(5)
(pÉq).~qÉ~p.
e. + (1) (p≡q) É (pÉq).
+(2)
(p≡q) É (qÉp).
(3) (p≡q) É (~pÉ~q).
(4) (p≡q) É (~qÉ~p).
(5) (p≡q).pÉq.
(6) (p≡q).qÉp.
(7) (p≡q). ~pÉ~q.
(8) (p≡q). ~qÉ~p.
f. (1) (pÉq) É(p∨rÉq∨r).
(2)
(pÉq) É( p.rÉ q.r).
(3)
(pÉ q) É[
(rÉ p)É(rÉ q)].
(4)
(pÉ q) É[
(qÉ r)É(pÉ r)].
(5)
(pÉ q).(
p∨r) É q∨r.
+(6) (pÉ q). (qÉ r) É(pÉ r).
(7) (p≡q).(p≡r) É( q≡r).
(8) (p≡q).(q≡r) É( p≡r).
g. (1)
(p≡q) É p∨r≡q∨r.
(2)
(p≡q) É (p.r≡q.r).
(3)
(p≡q) É[ (pÉ r)≡(qÉ r)].
(4)
(p≡q) É[ (rÉ p)≡(rÉ q)].
(5)
(p≡q) É[(p≡r)≡(q≡r)].
h. (1) (pÉ q). (rÉ s) É(p∨rÉ q∨s).
(2) (pÉ q). (rÉ s) .
(p∨r) É q∨s.
i. (1) qÉ(p≡p.q).
(2) ~q É (p≡p∨q).”[5]
Ayer’s
logical positivism also has certain influence in the
20th-century philosophical world, and his has many
philosophical works, and their quality is also relatively high,
but, as an overall characteristic, we think, Ayer’s originality in
philosophy is not sufficient; for example, about the property of
knowledge, he writes: “Much the same applies to the cases where
knowing is a matter of knowing how. Certainly, when people possess
skills, even intellectual skills, like the ability to act or teach,
they are not always consciously aware of the procedures which they
follow. They use the appropriate means to attain their ends, but
the fact that these means are appropriate may never be made
explicit by them even to themselves. There are a great many things
that people habitually do well, without remarking how they do them.
In many cases they could not say how they did them if they tried.
Nor does this mean that their performances are
unintelligent.”[6] Here, Ayer
discusses about the general characteristic of knowledge, and he
thinks not only things people are clearly aware of can be called
knowledge, and there is much knowledge which is not explicitly
expressed by language and consciousness, but is also intelligent,
and Ayer’s this view is certainly somewhat reasonable. But, we can
also know, about the philosophical problem of knowledge’s
characteristic, it is a basic problem which has been repeatedly
discussed by people since Plato and Aristotle, and in modern times,
many people such as Descartes, Locke and Leibniz also have
discussed about it, and it is actually already a somewhat old
problem, while Ayer seems not to add many essential new insights.
To conclude, Ayer’s philosophy emphasizes on the extensive and
complex interrelations between knowledge, experience, logic and
language, etc, which roughly belongs to the epistemology category,
and is not very interested in ontological problems, which all
reflect the general feature of British and American philosophy;
but, as for originality, he is relatively worse than Quine and
Carnap.
3 Husserl, Heidegger and Gadamer’s phenomenology,
existentialism and hermeneutics. Broadly
speaking, the phenomenology, existentialism and hermeneutics of
Husserl, Heidegger and Gadamer are also important branches of
20th-century philosophical world, and also have high
academic value. Firstly, as for Husserl, his phenomenology stems
from his critical reflection of scientific knowledge, which is
consistent with Nietzsche’s view; the basic starting point of his
theoretical system is clear, namely, he thinks scientific knowledge
(such as physical knowledge and biological knowledge) is object
which can be checked, while behind these scientific knowledge,
there is still one kind of transcendental knowledge, namely, the
knowledge of real life, and because they belong to the field of
ontological phenomenology, and thereby is better than empirical
scientific knowledge, and is more important, as he says: “Whatever
may be the chances for realizing, or the capacity for realizing,
the idea of objective science in respect to the mental world (i.e.,
not only in respect to nature), this idea of objectivity dominates
the whole universitas of
the positive sciences in the modern period, and in the general
usage it dominates the meaning of the word ‘science’. This already
involves a naturalism insofar as this concept is taken from
Galilean natural science, such that the scientifically ‘true’, the
objective, world is always thought of in advance as nature, in an
expanded sense of the word. The contrast between the subjectivity
of the life-world and the ‘objective’ the ‘true’ world, lies in the
fact that the latter is a theoretical-logical substruction, the
substruction of something that is in principle not perceivable, in
principle not experienceable in its own proper being, whereas the
subjective, in the life-world, is distinguished in all respects
precisely by its being actually experienceable.”[7] To sum up,
Husserl’s phenomenology emphasizes the importance of life-world
this phenomenological field, and the focal point is the empirical
and objective reflection on scientific knowledge, and he thinks the
overemphasis of the importance of scientific knowledge will result
in that people overlook the broad experience contained in
life-world; obviously, Husserl’s these views have great
illumination for the subsequent Heidegger, etc, because one of the
central ideas of Heidegger is also the reflection on modern
scientific knowledge.
Heidegger’s
existentialism also has extensive and profound impacts on the
20th-century art and philosophy, and about the basic
problem existentialism faces, he once writes: “Furthermore, in each
case Dasein is mine to be in one way or another. Dasein has always
made some sort of decision as to the way in which it is in each
case mine [je meines]. That entity which in its Being has this very
Being as an issue, comports itself towards its Being as its ownmost
possibility. In each case Dasein is its possibility, and it ‘has’
this possibility, but not just as a property [eigenschaftlich], as
some present-at-hand would. And because Dasein is in each case
essentially its own possibility,
it can, in its very Being,
‘choose’ itself and win itself; it can also lose itself and never
win itself; or only ‘seem’ to do so. But only in so far as it is
essentially something which can
be authentic-that is, something of its
own-can it have lost itself and not yet won itself.”[8] The meaning of
Heidegger’s this passage is clear, namely, he wants to investigate
the various living modes of man as Dasein, hence identify the best
and most authentic types, and for this, he does many analyses. On
the other hand, Heidegger’s philosophy mostly centers around
existentialism, and rarely involves other aspects such as
epistemology, history, law, politics and logic, which shows that
the range of his writing is not very broad, and I think this point
is not difficult to know.
Gadamer’s
hermeneutics also has rich and profound intension, and his
hermeneutics emphasizes the inheritance of traditional things, but
he thinks, in this process, we need to use dialogue and imagination
to proactively and critically treat these handed down things, and
should keep an open attitude; as a good illustration of the basic
idea of his hermeneutics, he once says: “It is not only that
historical tradition and the natural order of life constitute the
unity of the world in which we live as men; the way we experience
one another, the way we experience historical traditions, the way
we experience the natural givenness of our existence and of our
world, constitute a truly hermeneutic universe, in which we are not
imprisoned, as if behind insurmountable barriers, but to which we
are opened.” “A reflection on what truth is in the human sciences
must not try to reflect itself out of the tradition whose binding
force it has recognized. Hence in its own work it must endeavor to
acquire as much historical self-transparency as possible. In its
concern to understand the universe of understanding better than
seems possible under the modern scientific notion of cognition, it
has to try to establish a new relation to the concepts which it
uses. It must be aware of the fact that its own understanding and
interpretation are not constructions based on principles, but the
furthering of an event that goes far back. Hence it will not be
able to use its concepts unquestioningly, but will have to take
over whatever features of the original meaning of its concepts have
come down to it.”[9] In this
paragraph, Gadamer’s view towards tradition and hermeneutics is
clear, namely, he thinks we all live under the long tradition which
have handed down, but we also should not blindly accept the
tradition’s all contents, while should critically and openly
inherit them, and only in this way can we absorb their pith and
spiritual essence. By using the basic idea of hermeneutics, Gadamer
does extensive and profound investigations about
many things such as
science, philosophy and art, and they are also greatly
inspiring.
4 French philosophy of Sartre and Merleau
Ponty. As is
widely known, French philosophy is greatly impacted by German
philosophy, and has large difference in style with British and
American philosophy, for example, few French philosophers discuss
about epistemological problems such as logic, language and science,
while French philosophy’s correlations with art and literature are
closer; here, we prepare to take Sartre and Merleau Ponty these two
people as example and discuss about the general style and academic
meaning of the 20th-century French philosophy. Sartre’s
existentialism has certain impact on the 20th-century
politics, literature and philosophy, and it is what we all know,
but, compare with Heidegger and etc, his academic level is somewhat
worse, for example, he once writes: “If the being of phenomena is
not resolved in a phenomenon of being and if nevertheless we can
not say anything about being without considering this phenomenon of
being, then the exact relation which unites the phenomenon of being
to the being of the phenomenon must be established first of all. We
can do this more easily if we will consider that the whole of the
preceding remarks has been directly inspired by the revealing
intuition of the phenomenon of being. By not considering being as
the condition of revelation but rather being as an appearance which
can be determined in concepts, we have understood first of all that
knowledge can not by itself give an account of being; that is, the
being of the phenomenon can not be reduced to the phenomenon of
being. In a word, the phenomenon of being is ‘ontological’ in the
sense that we speak of the ontological proof of St. Anselm and
Descartes. It is an appeal to being; it requires as phenomenon, a
foundation which is transphenomenal. The phenomenon of being
requires the transphenomenality of being.”[10] In this
passage, Sartre is discussing about the nature of being, and he
thinks only static observing cannot provide reason for being, and
being still needs a transphenomenal foundation, namely, the being’s
action, and he thinks only by human’s proactive action can
individual get the authentic living method, and here, the views
Sartre expresses are somewhat clear. But, from this paragraph, we
can also see, compared with Heidegger’s thoughts, Sartre is worse
in certain aspects such as speculation of words, logic of thought
and academic depth, namely, the academic and professional quality
of Sartre’s thoughts is not sufficient.
Merleau
Ponty’s phenomenology also has certain influence in French
philosophical world, and his phenomenological research has certain
academic foundation, and the aspects involved are somewhat broad,
but his depth of thought is also not enough; for example, he
writes: “Once introduced, the notion of sensation distorts any
analysis of perception. Already a ‘figure’ on a ‘background’
contains, as we have seen, much more than the qualities presented
at a given time. It has an ‘outline’, which does not ‘belong’ to
the background and which ‘stands out’ from it; it is ‘stable’ and
offers a ‘compact’ area of colour, the background on the other hand
having no bounds, being of indefinite colouring and ‘running on’
under the figure. The different parts of the whole-for example, the
portions of the figure nearest to the background-possess, then,
besides a colour and qualities, a
particular significance.”[11] Merleau
Ponty’s this paragraph discusses about sensation and perception,
which is not a very fresh philosophical problem, and many
philosophers have already discussed about it, and moreover, we can
also see, compared with works like Critique of
Pure Reason (1781) by Kant in the
18th century
or The Principles of
Psychology (1890) by William James in the
19th century, Merleau Ponty’s related
thoughts not only do not achieve progress, but also have certain
retrogression. To conclude, about Merleau Ponty’s philosophical
research, we think it has certain academic value, but also should
not be overestimated.
5 Popper, Kuhn and Lakatos’s philosophy of
science. Philosophy of science by Popper
and etc also has a large impact on the 20th-century
scientific and philosophical world, certainly, considering the
realistic fact, its impact on philosophy is bigger than scientific
world. Firstly, as for Popper, the range of his exposition is much
broader than Kuhn and etc, and is also somewhat systematic and
coherent, as an example, about the basic condition scientific
theory should satisfy, he once says: “In order to make this idea a
little more precise, we may distinguish three requirements which
our empirical theoretical system will have to satisfy. First, it
must be synthetic, so that it may represent a non-contradictory, a
possible world. Secondly, it must satisfy the criterion of
demarcation, i.e. it must not be metaphysical, but must represent a
world of possible experience. Thirdly, it must be a system
distinguished in some way from other such systems as the one which
represents our world of experience.”[12] In this
passage, Popper thinks that scientific theory should be synthetic,
and should be the constructed product of human mind, but it also
must fit with the empirical field, and must have objective
verifiability, and thus, only by combining human mind’s
subjectivity and construction and objective experience’s
verifiability together can we get a good scientific theory, and
Popper’s this view is somewhat profound. Certainly, the contents of
Popper’s philosophy of science are very complex, involving many
different problems such as probability, quantum theory, relativity,
language, induction, etc, which can not be clearly articulated by a
few words, while these ideas also have high academic
value.
In terms of
Kuhn and Lakatos’s philosophy of science, their works also have
substantial intension, and have good academic foundations, though
their impact on professional scientists is somewhat small, they
also extend and deepen the range of human thought, and thereby,
have certain academic meaning. Generally speaking, the impact of
philosophy of science mainly embodies in humanity and social
sciences, for example, they have a large impact on intellectual
history, politics, economics and sociology, while their actual
impact on the scientific world is somewhat small; the emergency of
this basic phenomenon is not accidental, below we will discuss
about the cause of this issue.
Finally, we
also want to discuss about the interrelation between philosophy of
science and logical philosophy this interesting problem; if we take
specific philosophers as example, Carnap are interested in both
philosophy of science and logical philosophy, while Popper is
mainly interested in philosophy of science, but not good at logical
philosophy, Quine is familiar with logical philosophy, but does not
know much philosophy of science; in conclusion, from these
philosophers, we can know, philosophy of science and logical
philosophy have overlapping places, but also have many their own
features. In general, logical philosophy pays more attention to
problems such as logic’s symbolic deductions and language’s logical
form, while the scope of philosophy of science’s concern is
broader, and it cares about scientific knowledge’s developing
feature, theoretical basis, philosophical meaning, etc; in a word,
these two different fields are both somewhat broad, and also have
their own academic feature and internal value.
6 Political philosophy and ethical philosophy.
(II) The
Connections between Modern Philosophy and
Natural Sciences
As people’s
general common sense, philosophy and natural science always have
close connections, and among them, scientific subjects which have
the closest relationship with philosophy are probably mathematics,
physics and biology these three fields; but, different from the
18th and
19th centuries, in the
20th century, the relationship between
philosophy and natural sciences undergoes some fundamental changes,
below, we want to analyze the complex correlation between the
20th-century philosophy and natural sciences.
1 The scientific background of
philosophy. In
the 17th and
18th centuries, the connection between
philosophy and science is very direct and close, for example,
Descartes (1596-1650) and Leibniz (1646-1716) are both important
philosophers and important mathematicians, and in the
20th century, such kind of person does
not exist. The basic reason behind this phenomenon is simple,
namely, in the past three, four centuries, though the depth and
breadth of philosophy does not increase much, the breadth of
science enlarges a lot, and the depth also greatly deepens; we can
roughly think, the range of science in the
19th century is already more than twice
than the 17th and
18th centuries, while the
20th-century scientific knowledge is also twice than the
19th century, which directly results in
that scientific research becomes more and more profound and
difficult, and therefore, it becomes increasingly difficult for
philosophers to master modern science.
As a concrete
illustration of the above phenomenon, we want to give an
appropriate example, namely, the mathematician Leray’s work. As a
great mathematician, Leray does many profound works in topology and
partial differential equation, and they include: in 1934, Leray and
Schauder cooperated to generalize Brouwer’s fixed point theorem and
its mapping degree theory into Banach space and form the
topological degree theory, and they also built the Leray-Schauder
principle; through this tool, using mapping degree to estimate the
fixed point of the completely continuous operator, they could get
the solution of certain complex high order partial differential
equation, which has become the standard tool to study nonlinear
partial differential equation. In 1945, to make connections between
the local property of continuous mapping and global cohomology,
Leray first introduced sheaf theory and cohomology whose
coefficient is sheaf, and after the modification of Weil, Cartan
and Serre, it becomes the most efficient method to treat complex
space. In 1946, for the need of studying homotopy of fiber bundle,
Leray introduced locally compact space and spectrum sequence with
compactly supported cohomology continuous mapping, namely, the
Leray spectrum sequence, and used it to compute the homology of
fiber space, and got profound results. From 1957-1964, Leray did a
series of research about strongly hyperbolic operator, and
generalized F John’s method to strongly hyperbolic operator. In
general, Leray made important contributions in many aspects such as
boundary value problem, fixed point theory, hyperbolic partial
differential equations and Lagrangian analysis. Form this example,
we can see, Leray’s mathematical works are profound and extensive,
and even for professional mathematicians, it is also very difficult
to understand his relevant research, while for philosophers, it is
almost impossible to understand his work; to sum up, mathematicians
are working as hard as they can to understand works by Leray and
etc, and they do not have energy to study much obscure knowledge of
modern philosophy. To conclude, philosophy’s detachment from modern
science is not accidental, and the fundamental reason is that
modern science is becoming increasingly broad and profound.
Certainly, on the other hand, due to some philosophers of science
such as Carnap, Popper and Reichenbach, though the direct influence
of many research results of modern science on philosophy is
weakening, their indirect influence on philosophy is still very
extensive and strong.
2 The difference between mathematics and
logic. As
stated above, some philosophers are keen on studying logic, and the
extensive usage of mathematical logic and logical thinking method
is also a basic characteristic of the 20th-century
philosophy; but, from the perspective of mathematics, logic is just
a marginal branch of mathematics, and no matter in depth or
breadth, it cannot be compared with some major mathematical
branches such as analysis, algebra, geometry and
topology. Here, we can take
some specific logicians as example: Turing is a good logician, but
his level cannot be said too high, Godel’s academic achievement is
better than Turing, but also cannot be said
too great, namely, these important logicians’
academic contributions are far from some mathematicians like
Poincare, Hadamard and Weyl. In
a word, compared with other mathematical branches, logic is just a
somewhat shallow field, and also somewhat narrow, and I think it is
meaningful for philosophers to know this basic fact.
3 About modern
philosophers’ scientific foundation. One
basic feature of modern philosophical book is that many works are
all literary; for example, when we see the title of
Husserl’s Logical
Investigation, we
will probably think there should be many symbolic things in it, but
when we browse this book’s contents, we can see, there are almost
no symbolic deductions in this whole work; for example, Husserl
once says: “The concept of pure logic so far developed covers a
theoretically closed circle of problems, essentially relate to the
idea of Theory. To the extent that no science is possible without
grounded explanation, i.e. without theory, pure logic covers the
ideal conditions of the possibility of
science in general in the
most general manner. It
must, however, be noted that logic so regarded does not include, as
a special case, the ideal conditions
of empirical science in
general.”[14] What
Husserl discusses here is the nature of logical concept, and his
these words are certainly reasonable, but not symbolic. Ayer’s
situation is also similar, for example, when we see the title
of The Problem of
Knowledge, we
will often think that there are some symbolic contents, but this
book is actually also mostly literary. Certainly, it should be
noted that, Husserl has certain scientific foundation, and he
receives the mathematical PhD degree from University of Vienna in
1883, and his doctoral thesis is “The variational theory of
calculus”, but, the mathematical symbolic contents in his works are
not many.
Here, we also
want to examine other philosophers’ scientific mastery. As for
Carnap, though he has studied relativity, and
writes The Philosophical Foundation of
Physics this work, in fact, he can not
understand most contents of general relativity, because general
relativity is based on Riemannian geometry, while Carnap does not
quite know Riemannian geometry. Russell’s situation is roughly also
like this, for example, in The Analysis of
Matter, he discusses about many physical contents, such as the
“quantum theory” in chapter IV, “general relativity” in chapter VI,
and “Weyl’s theory” in chapter X, but his understandings towards
these physical theories are all superficial, and just with a vague
impression, for example, he once writes: “Riemann’s work, as well
as that of Faraday and Maxwell, belongs, like the theory of
relativity, to the development of the view of the physical world as
a continuous medium, which has, from the earliest times, contested
the mastery with the atomic view.”[15] In fact,
about the mathematical and physical knowledge in this paragraph,
such as Riemannian geometry and Maxwell’s electromagnetic theory,
Russell all does not really understand.
Considering
various kinds of situation, if comparing the scientific foundation
of modern philosophers, we think, it will probably be the following
order:
Carnap, Putnam, Frege >
Russell, Husserl > Ayer
Certainly, in
general, these philosopher’s scientific foundations are far from
professional scientists, and compared with some important
scientists in the 20th century, such as
Dirac, Grothendieck, Wiener and Wiles, no matter in breadth or
depth, modern philosophers’ scientific mastery is far from them.
However, conversely, professional scientists also do not quite know
some problems these philosophers discuss, such as logic, language,
ontology, positivism, existentialism, empiricism and etc, because
they lack professional knowledge in philosophy, and I think this
point is also not difficult to understand. To sum up, knowing these
basic facts will be quite meaningful for us to understand the
general feature of 20th-century philosophy.
(III) The
Connections between Modern Philosophy and
Humanity and Social Sciences
All along,
philosophy also has extensive and close connections with humanity
and social sciences, which is also a fact we are familiar with;
about the relationship between philosophy and social sciences,
Hegel once says: “But men do not at certain epochs, merely
philosophize in general, for there is a definite Philosophy which
arises among a people, and the definite character of the
stand-point of thought is the same character which permeates all
the other historical sides of the spirit of the people, which is
most intimately related to them, and which constitutes their
foundation. The particular form of a Philosophy is thus
contemporaneous with a particular constitution of the people
amongst whom it makes its appearance, with their institutions and
forms of government, their morality, their social life and the
capabilities, customs and enjoyments of the same.” “The history of
the other Sciences, of culture and above all the history of art and
religion are, partly in regard to the elements contained in them,
and partly to their particular objects, related to the history of
Philosophy.”[16]Hegel’s this passage makes a
good explanation about the complex and profound relationship
between philosophy and social sciences. To conclude, philosophy
needs to carefully consider the situation in social field,
including many aspects such as politics, economy, society, art,
religion and law, because these aspects all contain many meaningful
philosophical problems (like social justice, individual’s ethical
norm, aesthetics, etc), while if cutting off the extensive
connections between philosophy and social field, philosophical
research will become water without the source.
Take the
specific philosophers as example, they also can well embody the
extensive correlations between modern philosophy and social
sciences; for example, Heidegger and Sartre’s existentialism has
certain impact on political practice, Dewey’s education and
politics also comes from the observation and thinking about real
social life, Quine’s language philosophy stems from the systematic
reflection of many language phenomena in real life, Dworkin and
Rawls’s works in political philosophy also reflect many actual
problems in their time. Take the philosophical branches as another
example, some important philosophical branches in the
20thcentury, such as language philosophy, ethical
philosophy, existentialism and hermeneutics, also all use various
relevant issues in actual life as their empirical foundation. In
conclusion, obviously, many problems in social science field also
constitute part of driving force for the development of modern
philosophy.
(IV) About the
General Property of Philosophy
Finally, as an
appropriate summarization, we also want to discuss about the
general property of philosophy; people often say that, philosophy
is the subject of world view, while to form a complete world view,
philosophy needs to comprehensively consider the complex situation
in both natural sciences and humanity and social sciences, and as
the ancient Chinese thinker Chuang Tzu says: “Appreciating the
beauty of the world, analyzing the reason of everything, and
examining the ancient people’s thoughts. If one people can possess
the completeness of the world, then he can be called
saint.” [17] Chuang Tzu’s
these words do a good generalization about the holistic property of
philosophy. In philosophers’ view, only after the deep study about
many problems in the natural world and social field can one people
get a mature and wise view towards life and universe, and can he
get true wisdom, which is perhaps the goal philosophers always
pursue from ancient to modern times.
Generally
speaking, philosophy has both natural science attribute and social
science attribute, and is the combined product of them, thereby,
for philosophers, it is often insufficient to just study one side
of them; for example, about “truth” this important philosophical
problem, we can evidently feel this double attribute of philosophy.
As is widely known, philosophers like discussing the feature and
meaning of truth, while around “truth”, philosophers also have had
many intense debates; in general, we think, for scholars in
different fields, there are at least the following five kinds of
conceptions of truth:
1 Logical
positivism’s truth. In the eyes of logical positivists like Carnap,
only facts which can be reduced to basic empirical propositions are
truth, and the others are not objective truth, and as Carnap says:
“The system which is formulated in this book takes as basic
elements the elementary experiences. Only one basic concept is
used, namely a certain relation between elementary experiences
(recollection of similarity). It is then shown that the other
concepts, e.g. the different senses, the visual sense, visual field
places and their spatial relations, the colors and their relations
of similarity, can be defined on this basis.”[18] We can easily
see, it is one kind of truth which is mathematical and has strong
natural science feature.
2 Pragmatism’s
truth. In the eyes of pragmatists like William James, things which
can be checked and used in practice are truth, and the other things
are not truth, and as he says: “True ideas are those that we can
assimilate, validate, corroborate and verify. False ideas are those
that we can not. That is the practical difference it makes to us to
have true ideas; that, therefore, is the meaning of truth, for it
is all that truth is known-as.”[19]
3
Existentialism’s truth. While in the eyes of existentialists like
Heidegger, truth is another thing, namely, the freedom to achieve
one’s authentic condition is truth, and as Heidegger says: “The
essence of truth reveals itself as freedom. The latter is
ek-sistent, disclosive letting beings be. Every mode of open
comportment flourishes in letting beings be and in each case is a
comportment to this or that being. As engagement in the discourse
of beings as a whole such, freedom has already attuned all
comportment to beings as a whole.”[20]Obviously, Heidegger’s this
view is roughly a conception of truth with social science
attribute.
4 Natural
scientists’ truth. For natural scientists engaged in scientific
research, the definition of truth is normally simple and clear,
namely, conclusions which can be objectively checked and can be
derived from rigorous logic are truth, for example, Gauss’s
differential geometry, abstract algebra, statistical mechanics and
Maxwell’s electromagnetic theory are all truth.
5 Social
scientists’ truth. Many social scientists also often like saying
that he is pursuing truth, such as jurist, economist, political
scientist, historian, etc, and the truth in their eyes are probably
some objective legal, economic and historical facts, or some
somewhat true abstract theories.
To conclude,
in terms of truth, we can evidently feel that philosophy actually
has the double attribute of natural science and social science: the
truth problem involves both many facts in natural science and many
situations in social field, and only by comprehensively considering
these two aspects can we get somewhat reasonable views. In a
broader sense, general philosophical research also often needs to
consider many situations in both natural science and social science
these two different fields.
Certainly, it
is somewhat difficult for philosophical research to include both
natural science and social science, because these two fields are
both broad and complex, and it will cost one people huge energy to
well master them; if looking from the specific philosophers,
Aristotle, Descartes, Kant, James, Russell, Husserl have profound
attainments in both natural science and social science, while
Hegel, Dewey, Heidegger and Nietzsche are not very proficient in
natural science, and just know humanity and social sciences,
namely, in the exploration of the natural world and society,
different philosophers’ knowledge background and problem
consciousness have large difference. In general, as the subject of
world view, philosophy needs to consider the complex situations in
both natural sciences and social sciences these two broad fields,
and I think 20th-century philosophy also makes many
contributions in these problems.
[1] The above contents can refer
to Conceptual Notation and Related
Articles, Chapter I, Section 11, 12, Oxford University Press,
1972. Frege’s analyses about these issues are more complex and
systematic than our quotations here, and interested readers can
refer to the relevant expositions in the original work.
[2] Introduction to
Mathematical Philosophy, Chapter XIV, “Incompatibility and the
Theory of Deduction”, pp. 149, 150, Dover Publications, Inc,
1993.
[3] From a Logical Point of
View, Chapter I, p. 12, Haper & Row, Publishers, 1963.
[4] See the above book, Chapter
V, p. 87.
[5] Introduction To Symbolic
Logic and Its Applications, Chapter A, “The simple language A”,
p. 27, Dover Publication, Inc. 1958.
[6] The Problem of
Knowledge, Chapter I, “Common features of knowledge”, p. 8,
Macmillan & Co. LTD, 1956.
[7] The Crisis of European
Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, Part III, Section
34, p. 127, Northwestern University Press, 1970.
[8] Being and Time,
Chapter I, Section 9, “The Theme of the Analytic of Dasein”, p. 68,
Blackwell Publishers Ltd, 1962.
[9] Truth and Method,
“Introduction”, XXIII, Continuum Publishing, 2004.
[10] Being and
Nothingness, Introduction, Section II, “The phenomenon of being
and the being of the phenomenon”.
[11] Phenomenology of
Perception, Chapter 2, “‘Association’ and the ‘projection of
memories’”, p. 15, Routledge, 2002.
[12] The Logic of Scientific
Discovery, Part I, Chapter I, Section 5, “Experience as a
method”, Routledge, 2002.
[13] Taking Rights
Seriously, Introduction, pp. VIII, IX, Harvard University
Press, 1978.
[14] Logical
Investigations, Volume I, Chapter XI, Section 72, p. 160,
Routledge, 2001.
[15] The Analysis of
Matter, Chapter II, “Pre-Relativity Physics”, p. 22, Routledge,
1992.
[16] Lectures on the History
of Philosophy, Volume I, “Introduction”, B, pp. 53-55,
University of Nebraska Press, 1995. In this part, Hegel also
discusses spirit of the age and spirit of the people, and these
expositions have a large impact on the later social thoughts and
philosophical thoughts.
[17] Chuang Tzu,
“Heaven”
[18] The Logical Structure of
the World, “Preface to the second edition”, p. VII, University
of California Press, 1969.
[19] Pragmatism, Lecture
VI, p. 201, Longmans Green and Co., 1922.
[20] Pathmarks, “On the
Essence of Truth”, p. 147, Cambridge University Press,
1998.
加载中,请稍候......