A New
Examination on the Relationship between Science and
Philosophy
The internal
relationship between science and philosophy is undoubtedly one of
the central themes in western intellectual circle over the past two
thousand years, and with the constant development of both science
and philosophy, the basic appearance of this issue is also changing
without stop. In this paper, based on some latest results in
science and philosophy, we want to make certain somewhat
fundamental explorations about this basic issue.
(I) A Historical Retrospect of the
Relationship between Science and Philosophy
If we
take a macroscopic perspective to overlook the internal
relationship between science and philosophy, then, we can easily
see that, the relationship between them roughly goes through three
major phases:
(1) As is
generally known, before the
17th century, science was to some
extent a branch of philosophy, and philosophy then constituted the
main body of people’s basic world view. At this time, scientific
research and philosophical inquiry were often interweaving with
each other.
Take some
great scholars for example, in ancient Greece, Plato made a series
of fundamental contributions in philosophy, and his esteem for idea
laid the foundation of rationalism temperament in western culture
for more than two thousand years, and meanwhile, he also made some
substantial contributions in mathematics, and in them, the most
famous one is naturally his school’s classification of five kinds
of regular polyhedron (cube, regular tetrahedron, regular
octahedron, regular dodecahedron and regular icosahedron) which
extensively exist in the natural world. After Plato, the successive
Aristotle embodied the different thinking orientation in western
culture, who laid the thought foundation of empiricism philosophy;
in the classicMetaphysics, he thinks that
the particular is prior to the universal; and meanwhile,
Aristotle’s basic contributions in science are also widely known
and he is the important founder of a series of subjects, including
zoology, physics, logic and etc. To conclude, in the representative
figures of ancient Greece, they kept intellectual enthusiasm to
both philosophy and science simultaneously, and also did
groundbreaking significant contributions to both of them. This is
the first period of the relationship between science and
philosophy.
(2) When it advances to
modern times, the basic relationship between philosophy and science
begins to gradually undergo deep-level changes. In the
17th century, science and philosophy
are still concurrently developing and mutually promote. Take
Descartes as an example, he thinks that human reason is the source
of everything, as he says: “Observing this
truth: I am thinking therefore I exist, was
so secure and certain that it could not be shaken by any of the
most extravagant suppositions of the sceptics, I judged that I
could accept it without scruple, as the first principle of the
philosophy I was seeking.”[1] Compared with
Plato’s rationalism, Descartes pulls the eternal idea in the
external objective world into human internal mind’s innate reason,
which makes human’s subject status greatly stand out, and thus, he
expands the range of philosophy and changes western philosophy’s
problem consciousness, and brings modern philosophy into a new
stage of epistemology. In the meantime, Descartes’ significant
contributions in science are also well known: he systematically
develops analytic geometry (Fermat independently gets the basic
idea of analytic geometry), and also does many original basic
contributions in physics (like momentum conservation law,
refraction law of light, Newton’s first law of motion, and so on).
After Descartes, Leibniz inherits the rationalism tradition, and he
thinks: “For something to be in the understanding it suffices that
it can be found there. And the sources or basic proofs of the
truths we are discussing can be found there, and only there: the
senses can hint at, justify and confirm these truths, but they
can’t demonstrate their infallible and perpetual
certainty.”[2] Leibniz’s
insistence on the importance of innate reason is perhaps not novel
in the history of philosophy, and his real ingenious contribution
is probably his unique “monad theory” (it’s a pity that the monad
theory perhaps does not spark more ideas later on). On the other
side, in science, Leibniz is an encyclopedic scholar, and besides
the epoch-making contribution in the creation of calculus, he also
does important contributions in many fields like biology, geology,
medicine, probability, information science and etc.
At the
same time, with the development of science, philosophy and science
also begin to show a gradual seperation internal tendency, and at
this moment, professional scientists and philosophers appear, for
instance, famous philosopher Spinoza lacks basic understanding
about science, and also does not make any substantial scientific
contribution, while many scientists, like Huygens and etc, also
lack basic philosophical knowledge.
In the
18th century, all fields of science are
developing by leaps and bounds, while the research scope of
philosophy is also broad, but it is already difficult to say
exactly which scholars make original contributions. At this time,
in intelligentsia, the representative figure who is expert at both
science and philosophy is undoubtedly Kant, in the
book General Natural History and Theory of
Heavens, Kant puts forward the nebula
hypothesis of star formation, and he is also proficient in natural
sciences like natural history, geology, mineralogy, on the other
side, in Critique of Pure
Reason this eminent magnum opus, Kant makes
rich contributions for modern philosophy in many ways.
But,
the basic tendency that philosophy and science detach from each
other is more increasing. On one hand, for some German philosophers
like Hegel, Schelling, Fichte and so on, and some English
philosophers like Hume and Berkeley, they just have broad exposure
to philosophy and lack sufficient scientific training, for
instance, Hegel once used speculative method to deduce that there
exist 7 planets in solar system, which is naturally rather
ridiculous in today’s view. On the other hand, for some leading
figures in science, like mathematicians Laplace and Lagrange and
physicist Ampere, their knowledge structure merely concentrates on
scientific fields, and without enough philosophical
knowledge.
In the
19th century, the intellectual exchange
between science and philosophy is more and more weak, but not
completely cut off, at this time, famous people among scientists
who are proficient in philosophy include Poincare, Mach, and so on.
Poincare’s tremendous contributions in mathematics don’t need to
detailedly list, and some subjects he founds alone like the
qualitative theory of ordinary differential equation and algebraic
topology has a far-reaching global impact to modern mathematics,
and meanwhile, in philosophy, he is renowned for conventionalism
and his philosophical works, like Science and
Hypothesis, Science and
Method, Last
Meditation and etc, are all
widely spread. Mach’s contributions in mechanics are also
universally acknowledged, and his fierce criticism to Newtonian
Mechanics directly inspires Einstein’s inquiry in theory of
relativity, and he also has brilliant contributions in many other
areas, including acoustics, optics, thermology, fluid mechanics,
electricity, and from the basic fact that the flying speed is named
after Mach we can also feel his high status in physics. While
Mach’s philosophy, as a branch of positivism and empiricism, has a
large impact to Vienna Circle’s logical positivism, and he thinks:
scientific laws are fact summation derived from the experiments,
and they are created is for people to more easily understand the
complex data, and thus, scientific laws are not so much connected
with actual natural phenomena as related with human thinking.
Though Mach’s this basic view is idealist, the rich contents of his
philosophy also contain some enlightenting spiritual
elements.[3]
When
human society advances to the first half of the
20th century, great scientists who have
deep cultivation in philosophy include Einstein, Weyl, Whitehead,
etc.
As we
know, Einstein has a strong interest in philosophy in his lifetime
and also reads many philosophical books, Volume 1
of Collected Essays of Albert
Einstein contains many articles related to
philosophy, like “View on Kant’s and Mach’s philosophy”, “On
Bertrand Russell’s epistemology”, “Physics, philosophy and
scientific progress”, “Remark on Engels’ manuscript
of Natural Dialetic”, etc, from them, we
can easily see: Einstein is very familiar with many people’s
philosophical views, like Hume, Mach, Kant and Russell, and the
thought essence contained in these works is also integrated into
his organic thought system. These energetic philosophical ideas
also have a positive impact on Einstein’s scientific innovation,
for instance, he once points out Hume’s philosophy’s profound
enlightment for his creation of special relativity.
As one
of the greatest mathematicians in the
20th century, Weyl makes a series of
significant contributions in mathematical fields like topology,
differential geometry, analytic number theory, Lie group, etc; and
meanwhile, he also has broad knowledge in philosophy, and his
classic Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural
Scienceextensively discusses about epistemology, and quotes
views from more than one hundred philosophers and scientists, and
deeply explores many related topics. Weyl’s philosophical views are
constantly changing in his life, and broadly speaking, go through
Fichte’s idealism, Husserl’s phenomenology and transcendental
existentialism these three periods.[4] In conclusion,
similar to Einstein, Weyl also has a lifelong interest in
philosophy.
(3) From the second half
of the 20th century, the relationship
between science and philosophy enters into a new phase. On one
hand, the influence of philosophy on science is more weak, on the
other hand, whether philosophy itself has any substantial progress
also becomes a question. These two basic characteristics determine
new changes of their relationship.
At
this time, philosophers with certain scientific mastery are Putnam
and Tarski. As is well known, Putnam is proficient in quantum
mechanics and general relativity, and meanwhile, he makes a
critical breakthrough in Hilbert’s
10th problem, while Putnam’s
philosophical research covers a wide range, involving many branches
like language philosophy, philosophy of mind, religious philosophy,
etc, and in them, he all puts forward his many new views. While
Tarski specializes in topology, measure theory, mathematical logic,
set theory, etc, and in 1924 (he was only 23 then), he proposed the
Banach-Tarski paradox based on axiom of choice, and this renowned
theorem points out: when axiom of choice holds, for a
three-dimensional solid ball, we can get two solid balls completely
identical to the original ball through a series of rigid
transformations. Similar to many logicians, Tarski is also
interested in issues like “truth”, and his semantic and logical
analyses about truth has a wide influence on linguistic philosophy,
it is worth noting that: if we just make analyses about “truth”
from epistemology, then are possibly difficult to obtain any
substantial new development[5] ; but if we
relate it with mathematical logic, then are able to get some
enduring objective conclusions.
While
since the second half of 20th century,
major mathematicians, physicists and biologists with a strong
interest in philosophy are already few, for many leading scientists
like Serre, Grothendieck, Feynman and Chen Ning Yang[6] , they just
specialize in science. While it is not accidental that the
influence of philosophy to science is gradually weakening, and
there are some deep-level basic reasons behind, below, we want to
do some preliminary analyses about the roots of this basic
phenomenon.
(II)Some Central Themes of
Philosophical Epistemology from the Perspective of Modern
Science
With
the development of modern science, especially the huge development
of 20th century science, many
traditional philosophical themes in the past can be more maturely
and deeply understood now, and they at least include the following
issues:
1 About the nature of
mathematics. The nature of mathematics has
provoked many philosophers’ contemplation, and take Kant for
example, in Critique of Pure
Reason, he writes: “proper mathematical
propositions are always judgements a priori, and not empirical,
because they carry along with them the conception of necessity,
which cannot be given by experience.” “Arithmetical propositions
are therefore always synthetic, of which we may become more clearly
convinced by trying large numbers. For it will thus become quite
evident that, turn and twist our conceptions as we may, it is
impossible, without having recourse to intuition, to arrive at the
sum total or product by means of the mere analysis of our
conceptions.” [7] Here, Kant
emphasizes that mathematics’ basic characteristic as synthetic
proposition, and in the following chapters, he want to prove why
mathematical propositions as synthetic propositions have general
validity, and he thinks that the root of generality of mathematical
propositions is that time and space is the so-called “pure form of
sensuous intuition” (detailed discussions of it is in the latter
part of this paper). From Kant’s example, we can easily see that,
many philosophers have been probing “the nature of mathematics” and
keep high exploration enthusiasm, then what conclusions do they
get? Probably just some hollow literal writings, and these
inquiries do not make any substantial impetus to the theme in both
depth and breadth, but, the
20th century mathematics has splendid
achievements, here, we just list three subjects:
(1)Abstract algebra. Compared with higher algebra, the thought
system formed by central concepts in abstract algebra, like group,
normal subgroup, ring, ideal, field, and so on, is a new language,
and it greatly extends the range of algebra and deepens its depth.
As to the questions it resolves, field extension theory can solve
old problems like trisection of an angle, quadrature of a circle
(after field extension theory emerges, the resolution of trisection
of an angle is already natural and ripe), while Galois theory’s
fundamental theorem can solve deep problems like no roots of nth
degree polynomial equation exist. The view of structure permeates
the whole abstract algebra, and knowledge points of group like
fundamental theorem of group homomorphism and group direct product,
of ring like prime ideal and maximal ideal, and of field like field
extension, all vividly embodies the structural view of algebra. At
the same time, what abstract algebra studies is not merely abstract
structure and general concept, it also has many special cases, like
the special linear group of group theory, the polynomial ring and
integer ring in ring theory, and finite field and construction of
field extension in field theory are all vivid, interesting and
valuable special cases. Ideal is an elegant and pivotal basic
concept in ring theory, but if there is just ideal this single
concept and without the support of other important concepts,
abstract algebra’s thought system is also definitely thin and
hollow, it is through concepts like prime ideal, maximal ideal,
Noetherian rings and PID and the deep connections between ring
theory and field theory that ring theory’s thought system becomes
rich and full. Field extension is a very natural theory, and the
basic distinction between algebraic extension and transcendental
extension is a fundamental distinction of it, and it can be used as
an effective tool to solve trisection of an angle problem also
demonstrates the power of treating geometrical problems by
algebraic method. (The styles between using analytical approaches
to solve geometrical problems and using algebraic ones to solve
geometrical problems do exist large differences) Finally, the
fundamental theorem of Galois theory is a concluding theorem of
abstract algebra, and it reflects the graceful and concise internal
connections of intermediate field and automorphism group, and is
one of few epoch-making basic breakthroughs in abstract algebra.
The operative feature also permeates into the whole abstract
algebra, and people who have learned abstract algebra will have a
deep feeling about this feature, though operation is not the
internal aim of algebra, it is indeed its fundamental overall
style. In conclusion, abstract algebra great pushes forward the
holistic intension of mathematics.
(2)Functional analysis. The problem consciousness of functional
analysis is rooted in mathematical analysis and higher algebra, and
central contents like integral operator, differential operator,
Baire category theorem, compact operator all have inextricable
internal connections with the previous courses, and are the
deepening and extension of related concepts and ideas in the
previous courses. As to the questions it resolves, functional
analysis also solves many old problems, like Weierstrass’
construction of the function continuous and non-differential at
anywhere, which is a miracle in the eyes of
19th century analysts, but through
Baire category theorem, we can have a more natural and deep
understanding about it, namely, functions continuous and
non-differential at anywhere are second category sets, as another
example, for the convergent problem of Fourier series, we just have
somewhat elementary treatment in mathematical analysis, while
functional analysis has a more profound analysis about it. The
structural view in mathematical analysis is still not obvious,
while it is somewhat notable in functional analysis; Hilbert space
and Banach space are the research objects of functional analysis
(as the research topics of functional analysis, important examples
like Lp space, lp space, C[a,b] are all Banach space), while
important theorems like Hahn-Banach extension theorem, uniform
boundness theorem, open mapping theorem, and closed graph theorem
characterize the basic properties and internal structure of these
spaces. In terms of special cases, functional analysis contains
many beautiful examples, and Lp space, Fourier series are all
important and beautiful special cases. As an important type of
operator, compact operator is the important research topic of
functional analysis and it has some important basic properties, as
an abstract concept, it generalizes many valuable special cases,
and can let us feel the enormous power of continuously generalizing
and abstracting in mathematics. Finally, functional analysis also
has a far-reaching and broad impact on the subsequent mathematical
development, for instance, it provides the basic language for
partial differential equation, and also directly and widely
permeates into quantum mechanics.
(3)Real Analysis. Real analysis is the direct deepening of
mathematical analysis, and does not have much thought association
with algebra. It originates from some fundamental problems
tormenting the mathematical world in the
19th century analysis, like the
integrability of function, exchange of order of integration, and is
the direct extension in thought system of mathematical analysis.
For some deep questions like integrability of function,
mathematicians find out that they cannot effectively resolve it by
using sequence language like sequence convergence, and therefore,
in real analysis, they invent a series of new language, namely,
using set and measure to replace sequence, thereby thoroughly
solving these fundamental questions in analysis. As a basic concept
in real analysis, measurable set is defined through outer measure
and Caratheodory condition and is closely related with elementary
set. As we know, Lebesgue measure has basic properties like
countable additivity, upper continuity. Real analysis also deeply
studies the internal structure of Lebesgue measurable function.
Bounded variation function and absolutely continuous function are
two kinds of important functions, and they all have good properties
(like every bounded variation function has finite derivatives
almost everywhere; while the derivative of absolutely continuous
function is integrable, and the fundamental theorem of calculus for
Lebesgue integration holds now). Real analysis thoroughly resolves
the integrability of function, exchange of order of integration and
monotone convergence theorem these three basic problems, and lays a
solid foundation for modern analysis, and also provides stable
operational space for the subsequent courses (like harmonic
analysis). As for the overall style, real analysis is an elegant
and exquisite course, and there are many graceful and delicate
skills, and the basic conclusions it finally gets are also
harmonic, quite enchanting.
The
above discussed three subjects all belong to mathematical
developments in the first half of
20th century, and in the 1960s and
1970s, there was a new wave of intellectual revolution in the
mathematical world, and more complex and profound subjects like K
theory, abstract algebraic geometry and homological algebra rapidly
emerged, and they all changed the overall face of mathematics. To
sum up, the mathematical world’s holistic understanding about
mathematics is rapidly developing, but the philosophical world is
somewhat vague about this situation, and thus, their answer to the
old question “the nature of mathematics” is almost certain to be
empty and superficial.[8] This is
naturally a holistic effect brought by philosophical world’s
detachment from the mathematical frontiers.
2 Space-time view. In western
philosophy, space-time view also has caused much dispute, and as is
well known, Kant thinks that time and space are both ‘form of
sensuous intuition’, and he argues: “What then are time and space?
Are they real existences? Or, are they merely relations or
determinations of things, such, however, as would equally belong to
these things in themselves, though they should never become objects
of intuition; or, are they such as belong only to the form of
intuition, and consequently to the subjective constitution of the
mind, without which these predicates of time and space could not be
attached to any object?”[9] Here, the
first view belongs to Newton, the second one belongs to Leibniz,
while the third one belongs to Kant.
In terms of
the third view that time and space as ‘form of sensuous intuition’,
Kant makes some systematic expositions, and his expositions can be
divided into “metaphysical exposition’ and ‘transcendental
exposition’ these two parts. In them, Kant’s metaphysical
expositions about the conception of space have four points:
firstly, “space is not a conception which has been derived from
outward experiences”; secondly, “space then is a necessary
representation a priori, which serves for the foundation of all
external intuitions”; thirdly, “space is not discursive, or as we
say, general conception of the relations of things, but a pure
intuition”; fourthly, “space is represented as an infinite given
quantity.” After that, Kant gives the ‘transendental exposition’ of
conception of space, and he thinks: “how can an external intuition
anterior to objects themselves, and in which our conception of
objects can be determined a priori, exist in the human mind?
Obviously not otherwise than in so far as it has its seat in the
subject only, as the formal capacity of the subject’s being
affected by objects, and thereby of obtaining immediate
representation, that is, intuition; consequently, only as the form
of the external sense in general.”[10]
About Kant’s
these abstract expositions, the later philosophers have a lot of
discussions, and in them, Russell respectively refutes the four
arguments of Kant’s metaphysical expositions of conception of
space, and he argues: 1 “According to Kant, the eyes and the mouth
exist as things in themselves, and cause my separate percepts, but
nothing in them corresponds to the spatial arrangement that exists
in my perception.” “Kant holds that the mind orders the raw
material of sensation, but never thinks it necessary to say why it
orders it as it does and not otherwise.” 2 “I should emphatically
deny that we can imagine space with nothing in it. You can imagine
looking at the sky on a dark cloudy night, but then you yourself
are in space, and you imagine the clouds that you cannot see.” In
fact, Kant will also agree with Russell’s this view, and he also
does not recognize there exists pure space which can be separated
from all materials. 3Kant thinks that the space does not have the
concept of various parts, and part of it, the “spaces”, is still
the “space” itself, while Russell thinks : “To those who take, as
practically all moderns do, a relational view of space, this
argument becomes incapable of being stated, since neither ‘space’
nor ‘spaces’ can survive as a substantive.” 4Kant thinks: “Sensuous
perception’s infinity should be related with the infinity of space,
thus space is not a concept.”[11] While Russell
refutes: “It is difficult to see how anything infinite can be
‘given’.” [12] (From
Russell’s these multi-angle critiques of Kant, we can see that:
compared with Chinese culture, western culture’s perception of
space is indeed somewhat speculative, and also touches some basic
characteristics of space.)
To conclude,
we can see that, though western philosophical world’s speculations
about the conception of space have certain depth of thought, their
detachment from modern scientific knowledge is also obvious, and if
we just walk along the road of philosophy, we probably cannot get
some simple and important basic theories (like special relativity)
even if we spend several centuries’ time.
About the
metaphysical exposition about the conception of time, Kant’s
expositions have 5 points: firstly, “time is not an empirical
conception”; secondly, “time is a necessary representation, laying
at the foundation of all our intuitions”; thirdly, “on this
necessity a priori is also founded the possibility of apodeictic
principles of the relations of time, or axioms of time in general”;
fourthly, “time is not a discursive, or as it is called, general
conception , but a pure form of the sensuous intuition”; fifthly,
“the infinity of time signifies nothing more than that every
determined quantity of time is possible only through limitations of
one time lying at the foundation.” As to the transcendental
exposition about the conception of time, Kant writes: “Time is
nothing else than the form of the internal sense, that is, of the
intuitions of self and of our internal state. For time cannot be
any determination of outward phenomenon. It has to do neither with
shape nor position; on the contrary, it determines the relation of
representations in our internal state.”
To sum up,
the basic view Kant repeatedly argues is that time and space are
both not concepts, but forms of sensuous intuition, namely :“space
ad time, as the necessary conditions of all our intuitions, in
relation to which all objects are therefore mere phenomena, and not
things in themselves, presented to us in this particular manner.
And for this reason, in respect to the form of phenomena, much may
be said a priori, whilst of the thing in itself, which may lie at
the foundation of these phenomena, it is impossible to say
anything.”[13] About Kant’s
arduous intellectual effort, on one hand, we indeed have full
respect, however, compared with the vast achievements of modern
mathematics and physics, we can also feel its basic defect. Below,
we want to state some significant developments involved with the
fundamental characteristics of space and time in modern mathematics
and physics:
(1)Special
relativity. As is generally known, the concept of space-time in
classical mechanics is absolute time-space view, namely, Galileo’s
space-time view, and this theory thinks: for all the inertial
systems, mechanical laws have the same form, but the validity of
this basic space-time view has gradually been questioned with the
double impacts of experiment and theory. As one of the experimental
bases to lead to special relativity, Michelson-Morley experiment
finds out the speed of light is irrelevant to the reference frame,
and thus, Galileo’s space-time view shows profound internal
conflicts with Maxwell theory. In 1905, Einstein makes creative
fundamental solution to the chaotic condition of mechanics theory,
and puts forward the simple but hugely influential special
relativity, and two basic assumptions of this theory is principle
of relativity and principle of constancy of light speed, and from
these two basic assumptions, it is easy to deduce Lorentz
transformation, which is the central equation of special
relativity. From Lorentz transformation, we can deduce length
contraction, time dilation, relativity of simultaneity and weight
increasing these four basic effects, and meanwhile, the velocity
formula of relative movement also correspondingly deepens. Finally,
we can also get the extremely important mass energy equation. The
above descriptions are probably the main intension of special
relativity, and they form an organic thought system, which
revolutionizes the Galileo’s space-time view. Though the
mathematical deductions of special relativity are simple, and the
mathematical tools it uses are just some simple differential and
integral calculus, it has a profound physical intension, and also
has a comprehensive impact on the subsequent development of modern
physics.
(2)
Differential geometry, Riemannian geometry and Global differential
geometry. As is generally known, the research topics of
differential geometry are curves and surfaces, and in them, surface
is the major research object. The computation of length of curves
has been solved in calculus, and in differential geometry, it
introduces simple concepts like curvature and torsion, which
characterize some basic properties like bending degree of curve.
Similarly, some basic properties of surface, like area, tangent
plane, normal vector, also already have precise solutions in vector
analysis, while in differential geometry, mathematicians introduce
the Guassian curvature to describe the bending degree of surface,
and also introduce some other delicate concepts (like developable
surface, geodesic curvature, etc) ; basic objects like geodesic
line and minimal surface are also central topics of surface theory;
later, Gauss discovers that K is an intrinsic quantity through
complicated computations, and gets the so-called Gauss’s theorema
Egregium, which is a significant discovery and directly catalyzes
the birth of Riemannian geometry; Gauss-Bonnet formula is one of
the central conclusions in differential geometry, which is a direct
generalization of the sum of all the angles of a trianlge is 180
degrees in plane geometry, but has a much wider applicability. To
sum up, differential geometry enables people’s understanding
towards geometry to have an overall deepening.
Riemannian
geometry and global differential geometry also have their own
complex contents, and we do not elaborate here.
Generally
speaking, as Shiing Shen Chern says, the development of geometry
has gone through 5 basic stages, and the first two stages are
respectively Euclidean geometry and analytic geometry, and they are
already well known now. As to the third stage in the development of
geometry, Mr. Chern points out: “The third development is the
notion of group, which is a basic structure in mathematics”, “he
(Klein) builds geometry on the basis of group: a space has a
transformation group, which permits the spatial graph to move from
one position to another, and thus, once we have a group, we have a
geometry, and then we study the geometric properties of all graphs
which are unchanged under this transformation group.” Namely, group
theory integrates the discussions of geometry into unified
intellectual framework, which greatly improves the ordering degree
of the whole field. After it, “Riemann localizes geometry, which is
the fourth development of geometry.” “Riemann not only uses
coordinates, but also uses the differential of coordinates, and
thus localizes Cartesian geometry”, “Riemannian geometry is mainly
built on arc length s, and the square of differential of arc length
will equal quadratic differential form of the coordinate, and we
can use arc length to build a geometry, because we have ds, then
can compute the length of the curve connecting these two points,
namely, arc length.” What Mr. Chern says is naturally just some
simple notions in Riemannian geometry, but can also show the plain
original ideas of Riemannian geometry. Finally, “after
localization, we also need integration, and also need to extend it
to the whole space, which is arguably the fifth development of
geometry.” [14] The typical
feature of this stage is the wide application of the mathematical
tool algebraic topology.
(3)Algebra
and geometry. In the review article “Mathematics in the
20th century”[15] , Atiyah does
some explorations about certain basic characteristics of
mathematics, and he examines the two pillars of modern mathematics:
algebra and geometry. Firstly, he thinks: “Geometry is, of course,
about space, of that there is no question. If I look at the
audience in this room I can see a lot; in one single second or
microsecond I can take in a vast amount of information, and that is
of course not an accident. Our brains have been constructed in such
a way that they are extremely concerned with vision.” Therefore,
Atiyah concludes: “spatial intuition or spatial perception is an
enormously powerful tool.” “We try to put them into geometrical
form because that enables us to use our intuition. Our intuition is
our most powerful tool.” “The human mind has evolved with this
enormous capacity to absorb a vast amount of information, by
instantaneous visual action, and mathematics takes that and
perfects it.” To sum up, Atiyah thinks that modern geometry has
close basic connections with human’s spatial intuition, which is an
important means for human to understand the world.
While about
the nature of algebra, Atiyah thinks that it is related with time,
and he says: “Algebra, on the other hand, is concerned essentially
with time. Whatever kind of algebra you are doing, a sequence of
operations is performed one after the other and ‘one after the
other’ means you have got to have time. In a static universe you
cannot imagine algebra, but geometry is essentially static. I can
just sit here and see, and nothing may change, but I can still see.
Algebra, however, is concerned with time, because you have
operations which are performed sequentially and, when I say
‘algebra’, I do not just mean modern algebra. Any algorithm, any
process for calculation, is a sequence of steps performed one after
the other; the modern computer makes that quite clear. The modern
computer takes its information in a stream of zeros and ones, and
it gives the answer.” Through Atiyah’s clear expositions, we can
easily see that, algebraic operations do have essential connections
with time.
Atiyah’s
analyses about some basic characteristics of geometry and algebra
naturally can extend our overall understandings about time and
space.
To conclude,
modern mathematics and physics have advanced the discussions about
time and space to a considerable depth, which is hard to imagine
for the speculative philosophers who are not familiar with modern
mathematics and physics, furthermore, Kant thinks that time and
space are so-called forms of sensuous intuition, and are related
with human’s practical activities, which I think is presumably
nonsense, because mathematics, time and space are all basic
inherent properties of the universe, which are completely
irrelevant with human’s subjective practical activities, and also
do not have any connection with human’s perceptual experience, and
I think this point can be deduced as a final conclusion.
Certainly,
western philosophy’s discussions about space-time view sometimes
also have deep insights, and Whitehead once expounds Descartes’
philosophy of time and space :“He concieves extension as one
fundamental attribute of the material, and we can summarize his
notion as this: the ultimate fact is not static substance, but the
stream of physical existence. We can name this stream and its
content and any part of the fullness of occasional presence as an
event: extension is the fundamenal attribute of things, and also
the fundamental attribute of process. But the evolution of nature
cannot be compressed in a continuous linear time process, and it
needs such kind of process without the limit of quantity to fulfil
this complete insight.”[16] We can easily
see, Descartes’ this basic idea is highly consistent with theory of
relativity. In the eyes of scholars under pure eastern culture’s
influence, time and space are deeply related with motion, which
seems somewhat incredible, but in the profound tradition in western
philosophy, the deep discussions about extension and time are
already voluminous, and thus, Einstein who is very familiar with
western philosophy can put forward theory of relativity is also a
natural consequence.
Through the
above complicated discussions, we can get the following basic
conclusion: the inquiry of time and space issue must be based on
broad and deep modern scientific knowledge, and though
philosophical dicussions also possibly contain some valuable
thought nutritions, they should be in the ancillary position,
because philosophical speculations contain many ludicrous views,
and meanwhile, if philosophical speculations do not have the
assistance of mathematical formulas, then they also will not get
any substantial scientific conclusion, and thus, are also hard to
have direct impact on human’s material life.
3 Probability. Since ancient
times, the philosophical world has done much exploration about the
complex theme of the relationship between necessity and
probability, while such kind of exploration mainly concentrates in
the social areas, for example, Schopenhauer once writes: “The life
journey of one person is completely not determined by himself, but
decided by other two factors-a series of accidental events and his
treatment of these events, and these two factors continuously
interact and adjust to each other.”[17] Philosophers’
these discussions are certainly also valuable, but compared with
them, the scientific community’s research about probable events is
undoubtedly more profound, precise and complex.
As is
generally known, in the 1920s, the great mathematician Kolmogorov
founded the axiom system of modern probability, and he put
probability in the theoretical background of measure theory to do a
holistic examination, and an event space is defined as a special
measurable set, probability function is defined as a measurable
function, and expectation is defined as the integration of
probability function, and he further proved the simple and basic
large number law. Modern probability also introduces basic concepts
like conditional expectation, and these concepts and theorems
interweave with each other, which together constitute the complete
thought system of probability.
To conclude,
the discussions about probability maybe need dividing into two
basic parts: in social fields, we need speculative philosophy and
science to together explore, while in the natural domain, what we
need is just modern science.
4 Quantum mechanics. As is well
known, in the 1920s, European intelligentsia bursts forth the
exciting revolution of quantum mechanics, which thoroughly reforms
Newtonian mechanics. In the theoretical system of quantum
mechanics, Heisenberg equation is the foundation of matrix
mechanics, while Schrodinger equation is the foundation of wave
mechanics, and the significant Dirac equation is the Schrodinger
equation considering relativistic effects. In wave mechanics, the
integration of the square of wave function is the probability
distribution of a particle in one area, and the state space of
quantum mechanics is a Hilbert space. Today, quantum mechanics has
permeated into the general culture of human society, and many
conclusions have become familiar-sounding common sense.
After the
birth of quantum mechanics, it also provokes much philosophical
discussion, for instance, Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle has
provoked extensive discussion about certainty and uncertainty, but,
unfortunately, since these so-called philosophical speculations
lack efficient support of scientific knowledge, thus, most of them
has become empty and does not get certain substantial
conclusions.
5 The so-called “how are synthetic judgments a priori
possible”. “Synthetic judgments a priori”
issue is the central theme of Kant’s epistemology, and in the
‘Introduction’ part of Critique of Pure
Reason, Kant raises this question: “How are
synthetic judgments a priori possible?”[18] If we
translate this seemingly obscure sentence, its meaning is actually
simple, namely, mathematics and natural sciences are all synthetic
judgments a priori (Kant thinks mathematics is not analytical
judgement, 5+7=12, cannot be obtained by analysis, but is related
with perceptual experience, thus, is a kind of synthetic judgment),
why do they have universal necessity? In other words, the question
Kant puts forward here is: why do mathematics and natural sciences
have universal applicability? The universal effectiveness of
scientific truth (such as mathematical knowledge like partial
differential equation, and physical knowledge like statistical
mechanics) is an obvious objective fact, which Kant does not doubt,
and what he questions here is, why do they have universal
effectiveness?
About
mathematics’ universal applicability, Kant’s answer is: the
foundation of mathematics-time and space, are both ‘form of
sensuous intuition’, and they ensure mathematics’ universal
necessity, while for the universal necessity of natural sciences,
Kant’s answer uses the twelve categories as the theoretical
basis.
From the
viewpoint of science, Kant’s speculative answer is certainly empty,
even ridiculous, and for the reason why mathematics has universal
applicability, I think we can only answer it from the inherent
characteristic of mathematics itself, for instance, the basic fact
that harmonic function has infinite differentiability is the result
of strict mathematical deductions, which has nothing to do with
space and time as ‘form of sensuous intuition’; every mathematical
course starts from several original concepts and original axioms,
and the following deductions conform to the strictness of logic,
and thus, they certainly have universal necessity. Natural
sciences’ universal necessity is also like this.
I think today
in the 21st century, there are few
professional scientists who will worry about mathematics’ universal
effectiveness, or, natural sciences’ universal effectiveness,
because the bedrock of modern science is very solid, and meanwhile,
in the exploration process of rigorousness of modern science’s
foundation, we should attribute almost all the essential
contributions to professional scientists (like in the second crisis
of mathematics, Cauchy introduces the basic idea of sequence
convergence to characterize the limit, and Weierstrass introduces
the fundamental concept uniform convergence to clarify the chaotic
condition in function series, while Dedekind builds the axiomatic
definition of real number system), which have little to do with
speculative philosophers.
Here, one
question which really needs inquiring is: why do there exist these
beautiful and complex basic laws in the universe? This point is
probably what Kant really wants to explore. If we ask: why do there
exist these elegant and abstract basic structures in the universe?
For this basic question, I think that no scientist can answer it,
because before we explore a concrete unknown question, no scientist
can guarantee that a certain conclusion (for instance, whether
Riemann Hypothesis is correct) must be true, or must be wrong, and
only after proofs or experimental observations can we make definite
conclusions. The order of universe is very awesome, but, I think
nobody can answer why the universe complies with these elegant and
abstract basic laws.[19] Certainly, we
can get some ambiguous conclusions, for instance, mathematics’
every step of development is very natural: from differential
geometry to Riemannian geometry to global differential geometry,
the research topics of differential geometry go through a natural
extension process, while the deepening of algebraic geometry’s
thoughts is also unadorned, from abstract algebra to homological
algebra, the deepening of algebra is also dominated by some simple
basic ideas. What we can get are just some general conclusions, but
the question why do there exist these universal and beautiful
internal rules in universe, is never able to completely solve.
Here, it is worth adding that, the universe is not that extremely
harmonious as we imagine: for instance, in geometry, trisection of
an angle cannot be done, as another example, in algebra, polynomial
equations of more than five degrees do not have unified root
formulas, and moreover, in analysis, most Lp spaces are not Hilbert
space, in physics, parity nonconservation is also a simple example.
To sum up, the universe is neither that inharmonious nor that
absolutely harmonious (as many scientists with strong aesthetic
temperament mistakenly think), it is a proper moderation, a proper
beauty.
6 Primary qualities and secondary
qualities. In the long history of
philosophy, the intense debate about primary qualities and
secondary qualities has lasted for several hundred years, and Locke
first extracts this well-known question, and he writes:
“qualities thus considered in bodies are of two kinds.
First, there are those that are utterly inseperable from the body,
whatever state it is in. Qualities of this kind are the ones that a
body doesn’t lose, however much it alters, whatever force is used
on it, however finely it is divided.” While
“Secondly, such qualities which in truth are nothing in
the objects themselves, but powers to produce various sensations in
us by their primary qualities, i.e. by the bulk, figure, texture,
and motion of their insensible parts, as colours, sounds, tastes,
etc.”[20]
The later
philosophers generally think that time and space belong to primary
qualities, while colours, sounds, tastes belong to secondary
qualities. Philosophers think that time and space as the material’s
attributes are different from colours and tastes, though they are
all material’s attributes, time and space have more objective
sociality; while if we think that time and space belong to
material’s feature, and are related with perceptual practice, this
view is undoubtedly somewhat ridiculous, because time and space are
basic properties of the universe, and do not have any perceptual
connection with human society, and it is a simple basic fact.
Meanwhile, colours, sounds and tastes are probably also excited by
material particles, and these objects’ molecules are also objective
things, and their connections with individual perceptions are also
not essential, and thus, what kind of differences between the
so-called primary qualities and secondary qualities does not have
too much significance. Certainly, the speculations of primary
qualities and secondary qualities have stimulated people’s deep
research about many concrete biological problems in seeing, hearing
and smelling, which is probably the real value of this debate.
Whitehead once comments :“This theory takes part in the battle of
modern science. Not only for physics, but also for biology, on
guiding scientific research into fruitful fields, this theory has
fundamental contributions.”[21] To sum up,
the debate between primary qualities and secondary qualities once
plays an important role in inspiring scientific research, but if
just limited in the scope of philosophical speculations, and not
extends the antennas in fields like physics and biology, the
meaning of this famous debate probably is not notable.
7 The long debate between empiricism and
rationalism. The long-standing debate
between empiricism and rationalism is naturally the main line in
the developing process of western philosophy, and the views of both
sides have fought for hundreds of years. Empiricism’s spokesmen
include Locke, etc, and he says: “In that all our knowledge is
founded; and from that it ultimately derives itself. Our
observation employed either, about external sensible objects, or
about the internal operations of our minds perceived and reflected
on by ourselves, is that which supplies our understanding with all
the materials of thinking.”[22] While
rationalism’s spokesmen include Leibniz, etc, and he writes:
“everything inscribed on it (the soul) comes solely from the senses
and experience; or whether the soul inherently contains the sources
of various notions and doctrines, none of these comes from external
objects, whose only role is to rouse up the notions and doctrines
on suitable occasions.”[23] Here, the
differences between the two sides is somewhat obvious, certainly,
no matter for Locke or Leibniz, their philosophical systems are
both very complicated, which cannot be mechanically differentiated,
but the thinking orientations of them do have obvious basic
differences.
While Kant who later enters the
historical arena tries to reconcile these two continuously
conflicting thought lines. He writes: “Our knowledge springs from
two main sources in the mind, first of which is the faculty or
power of receiving representations (receptivity for impressions);
the second is the power of cognizing by means of these
representations (spontaniety in the production of conceptions).
Through the first an object is given to us; through the second, it
is, in relation to the representation (which is a mere
determination of the mind), thought. Intuition and conceptions
constitute, therefore, the elements of all our knowledge, so that
neither conceptions without an intuition in some way corresponding
to them, nor intuition without conceptions, can afford us a
cognition.” “We apply the term sensibility to the receptivity of
the mind for impressions, in so far as it is in some way affected;
and, on the other hand, we call the faculty of spontaneously
producing representations, or the spontaneity of cognition,
understanding.” “Without the sensuous faculty no object would be
given to us, and without the understanding no object would be
thought. Thoughts without content are void; intuitions without
conceptions, blind.”[24] To sum up,
Kant thinks that our knowledge is together constituted by
sensibility and understanding, and perceptual knowledge comes from
experience, while rational knowledge comes from the integration of
our inner thinking, which is the central argument Kant repeatedly
emphasizes in Critique of Pure
Reason.
Actually, in
Locke’s epistemology, there are also expositions similar to Kant’s,
and he writes: “how men ,barely by the use of
their natural faculties, may attain to all the knowledge they have,
without the help of any innate impressions; and may arrive at
certainty, without any such original notions or
principles.”[25] “The power of
thinking is called the understanding, and the power of volition is
called the will; and these two powers or abilities in the mind are
denominated faculties.”[26] From this, we can
easily see, Locke actually also thinks that people have some
natural inner abilities and inner psychological structure, but
different with Leibniz, he thinks that there are no innate
impression nor innate knowledge in human mind. The reason why Locke
holds such wise views is not difficult to understand, because human
needs understanding concepts to integrate messy external
representations, which is an obvious simple fact, and Kant only
endows it with enormous speculative depth.
Therefore,
people like Locke are actually all difficult to be called real
thorough empiricists, and due to the richness of these scholars’
thoughts, thus, they all have an internal thought orientation to
fuse experience and reason these two things. If we give an
appropriate example of the debate between empiricism and
rationalism, one scenario Goethe depicts is perhaps most proper,
and he once vividly describes the interesting meeting when he first
gets to know Schiller, and he writes: “Not separately, individually
study the nature, but creatively, actively, and trying to from the
whole to the parts describe the nature. He wants to clarify about
this, but does not conceal his suspect, and he couldn’t admit that,
such kind of situation, as I have emphasized, stems from
experience.” “At that time, I am enthusiastically expounding the
plant’s metamorphosis and try to use some typical drawings to let a
symbolic plant appear before him. He listens, and watches all this
with much interest, with obvious receptivity; but when I finish
this talk, he shakes his head and says: this is not experience, but
is a view. I am stunned, with some anger.”[27] Here,
Goethe’s empirical view and Schiller’s rational view have a severe
conflict. Certainly, we can easily know now, both of their basic
views have big problems, and a plant is mainly an organism composed
of roots, stems, leaves, flowers, fruits, and seeds these six
organs, and we need to do systematic scientific research about
them, which is perhaps neither experience nor reason, and no matter
the concept of experience or the concept of reason, compared with
the extremely complex botanical concrete knowledge, are both too
empty.
What modern
biology can solve is naturally not only this small debate of Goethe
and Schiller about plant’s metamorphosis, and what it can resolve
are fundamental problems in philosophical epistemology. As stated
above, Kant thinks that, human knowledge comes from the composition
of sensibility and understanding, and in them, understanding
belongs to human’s natural innate ability, and this basic view is
naturally plain and right, here, modern biology can provide us with
strong arguments. We want to first give a simple example, and in
the above quoted article “Mathematics in the
20th century”, Atiyah writes: “Vision,
I understand from friends who work in neurophysiology, uses up
something like 80 or 90 percent of the cortex of the brain. There
are about 17 different centers in the brain, each of which is
specialised in a different part of the process of vision: some
parts are concerned with vertical, some parts with horizontal, some
parts with color, or perspective, and finally some parts are
concerned with meaning and interpretation.” What Atiyah says is
certainly just a small conclusion in neurophysiology, though the
development of today’s neurophysiology encounters somewhat big
obstacles, the concrete results it gets already make the empty
discussions in philosophical epistemology eclipsed. As early as 100
years ago, in the era of William James, neurophysiology already
gets many definite conclusions; take the vision Atiyah discusses
for example, as William James says: “Munk almost immediately
declared total and permanent blindness to follow from destruction
of the occipital lobe in monkey as well as dogs, and said that the
angular gyrus had nothing to do with sight, but was only the center
of tactile sensibility of the eyeball.”[28] “He (Munk)
was the first to distinguish in these vivisections between
sensorial and psychic blindness”; “the first to notice the hemiopic
character of the visual disturbances which result when only one
hemisphere is injured. Sensorial blindness is absolute
insensibility to light; psychic blindness is inability to recognize
the meaning of the optical impressions, as when we see a page of
Chinese print but it suggests nothing to us. A hemoipic disturbance
of vision is one in which neither retina is affected in its
totality, but in which, for example, the left portion of each
retina is blind, so that the animal sees nothing situated in space
towards its right.”[29] “the
occipital lobes have frequently been found shrunken in cases of
inveterate blindness in man.”[30] To sum up,
William James’ expositions about vision are somewhat rich, and
these rich knowledge are all rooted in the overall development of
neurophysiology.
From the
above concrete expositions of physiological knowledge about vision,
we can clearly know that, the heated debate about reason and
experience in philosophical epistemology must resort to the
definite knowledge in biology to resolve, while what biology’s
neurophysiology gets is undoubtedly strong knowledge; if we trace
the source of Kant’s so-called human intellectual ability, it is
naturally controlled by many cells in brain center. Generally
speaking, we can get the following basic conclusion: it is too
deviod to use ambiguous concepts like sensibility or understanding
to describe human’s cognitive process, and they perhaps provide
certain exploration frameworks, but, compared with extremely rich
concrete neurophysiology knowledge, are definitely somewhat
coarse.
The
fundamental reason why the philosophical world’ opinions are
divided about empiricism and rationalism this central issue is due
to neurophysiology’s high complexity and abstruceness, as is well
known, the overall field of neurophysiology is very difficult,
which possibly cannot be solved even by the
22nd century. Biology currently is only
in its embryonic period, and basic achievements which can support
the whole field’s development are not very many, while as the most
abstruce field in biology, neurophysiology’s development is even
more in the very initial stage. Therefore, neurophysiology’s
research has not obtained sufficient research results, which
determines that the philosophical world has argued for such a long
time on the fundamental problem about whether knowledge comes from
experience or reason; considering neurophysiology’s current
development, this heated debate probably will still last for some
time.
8 The influence of philosophy of
science. As we know, the representative
figures of philosophy of science include: famous philosopher Karl
Popper who holds critical rationalism, the author of the widespread
classic Proofs and Refutations: The Logic of
Mathematical
Discovery Lakatos, historian
of science Kuhn who put forwards the original idea of scientific
paradigm theory, and Feyerabend who claims scientific relativism.
We must point out that, philosophy of science plays certain
positive functions in clarifying some basic features of scientific
knowledge (like Popper’s ‘falsifiability’), and distinguishing
certain trends of scientific development (like mathematical
knowledge’s empirical property Lakatos discovers[31] ), etc, thus,
philosophy of science also enriches human knowledge domain, and
broadens and deepens human’s cognitive perspective. But, for
professional scientists, we perhaps do not need too much concrete
knowledge in philosophy of science, and as the famous physicist
Weinberg says: “The philosophy of science is just about as useful
to scientists as ornithology is to birds.” Though this sentence is
somewhat biting, it also includes some truth. Because, on one hand,
compared with concrete knowledge in modern mathematics and physics,
philosophy of science’s theory is somewhat too hallow, on the other
hand, knowledge in modern mathematics and physics is already vast
and difficult, and scientists already make every effort to learn
these knowledge, and do not have spare energy to learn these
obscure philosophical ideas. Thus, philosophy of science has
certain thought value, but should not be overestimated.
Here, about
the influence of philosophy of science, we can more specifically
examine the situation in the scientific community. Firstly, as for
certain scientific scholars, if we ask some important
mathematicians and physicists in the second half of the
20th century, like Lax, Chern, Selberg,
Hirzebruch, Milnor, Smale, Gell-Mann, Feynman, and Landau, whether
they have been impacted by philosophy of science. I think they will
probably all say that they are not familiar with some philosophers
of science, like Popper, Kuhn, Lakatos, Schlick and Carnap, and
even are not familiar with well-known philosophers in the
17th and
18th century like Kant, Locke and Hume,
but, they still do many brilliant scientific contributions, which
fully shows that philosophy of science’s actual influence on
scientists is actually very small; secondly, for the whole
scientific community, as most scientific workers can feel,
philosophy of science’s impact on the whole scientific world
(mathematics, physics, chemistry, etc) is also weak. (Certainly,
some great scientists, like Heisenberg and Schrodinger, have a
somewhat strong interest in philosophy, but they are just minor
cases, and philosophy’s impact on
20th century science is somewhat small,
which I think is a basic fact most professional mathematicians and
physicists will agree with, certainly, this fact itself is not
necessarily good, after all, philosophical speculations once played
a very positive role in scientific research before the
20th century, and therefore, about the
value of philosophy of science, we should dialectically view.) To
conclude, if we combine the facts in many aspects together and
comprehensively consider, about the value of philosophy of science,
I think it is, to a large extent, more close to liberal art
subjects like sociology, philosophical epistemology and
intellectual history, while its connection with the scientific
world is not very close, namely, the field philosophy of science
probably belongs to cross-discipline field between science and
humanities, and thus, about its internal value, we also need to
respectively consider its complex impacts in natural sciences and
humanities, which I think is a basic fact we need to
identify.
If
summarizing the above complex discussions, we can get three basic
conclusions: firstly, the function philosophical epistemology plays
in mathematics and physics is already small, while in the
perspective of modern mathematics and physics, some fundamental
problems the philosophical world has argued for a long time can get
somewhat complete answers. Therefore, in mathematics and physics,
pure speculative philosophical discussions perhaps are already
somewhat meaningless. Nowadays, there exists a universal
phenomenon: after some philosophers get certain vague
understandings about special relativity, quantum mechanics,
algebraic topology and Riemannian geometry, they begin to talk
about their so-called philosophical intension, but, it is actually
not an easy thing to get precise understandings about certain
scientific knowledge, for instance, even for the somewhat simple
special relativity, I repeated over fifty times in the process of
mastering it; I personally think: before we can solve all the
after-school problems in special relativity, one person is not
eligible to talk about its so-called philosophical meaning.
Secondly, in fields like biology and linguistic, due to the high
complexity of neurophysiology, some old philosophical debates will
still continue. Thirdly, the universal decline of philosophical
epistemology’s influence in the latter part of the
20th century is a natural result of
philosophical world’s detachment from the frontiers of modern
mathematics, physics, biology, etc.
Certainly, it
is also difficult to affirm that, the philosophical world’s vast
discussions about many issues, like time, space, experience,
consciousness, etc, are really meaningless, and the
basic
phenomenon that leading scientists lack
profound philosophical mastery in modern science is also rather
regrettable; because the intellectual exchange between science and
philosophy once lasts for two thousand years, and it is proved that
this intellectual interaction is meaningful (refer to examples like
Einstein and Weyl), and the high speculation of philosophical
exploration perhaps can still provide us with some valuable
spiritual nutrients, and therefore, it is also a quite meaningful
thing for professional philosophers to have certain philosophical
mastery.
As a
supplement of the discussions about the relationship between
philosophical epistemology and modern science in the above, below
we want to analyze the intricate connections between experience and
scientific research.
9
Experience and scientific research. When
our analytical perspective turns to the intriguing theme about the
relationship between experience and scientific research, firstly,
we will encounter one popular view, namely: experience is of little
value to scientific research; but, Dewey corrects people’s this
universal prejudice, and he says: “They indicate that experience,
if scientific inquiry is justified, is no infinitesimally thin
layer or foreground of nature, but that it penetrates into it,
reaching down into its depth, and in such a way that its grasp is
capable of extension; it tunnels in all directions and in so doing
brings to the surface things at first hidden-as miners pile high on
the surface of the earth treasures brought from below.” Using the
geologist’s work method as an example, Dewey describes: “The
geologist did not leap from the thing he can see and touch to some
event in by-gone ages; he collated this observed thing with many
others, of different kinds, found all over the globes; the results
of his comparisons he then compared with data of other experiences,
say, the astronomer’s. He translates, that is, observed
coexistences into non-observed, inferred sequences.” Namely,
human’s primitive experience is important material of scientific
research, and in the process of scientific research, human’s
primitive experience is processed, refined and abstracted into some
secondary scientific knowledge, in other words, human’s primitive
experience is always one of the most important and extensive
materials in scientific research. Based on biological knowledge,
Dewey continues to analyze: “For the natural sciences not only draw
their material from primary experience, but they refer it back
again for test. Darwin began with the pigeons, cattle and plants of
breeders and gardeners.” “Scientific men, whether they accepted his
theories or not, employed his hypothesis as directive ideas for
making new observations and experiments among the things of raw
experience-just as the metallurgist who extracts refined metal from
crude ore makes tools that are then set to work to control and use
other crude materials.” Dewey further summarizes the basic
relationship between scientific theory and empirical materials:
“Theory may intervene in a long course of reasoning, many portions
of which are remote from what is directly experienced. But the vine
of pendant theory is attached at both ends to the pillars of
observed subject-matter. And this experienced material is the same
for the scienfic man and the man in the street. The latter cannot
follow the intervening reasoning without special preparation. But
stars, rocks, trees, and creeping things are the same material of
experience for both.” Finally, as the summary of the above
complicated arguments, Dewey writes: “wherein experience presents
itself as the method, and the only method, for getting at nature,
penetrating its secrets, and wherein nature empirically disclosed
(by the use of empirical method in natural sciences) deepens,
enriches and directs the further development of
experience.”[32] In a word,
actual empirical materials are fundamentally important for
scientific research, which is somewhat inconsistent with our common
imagined science’s rationalism feature, but it is indeed a
complex issue requiring our serious
consideration.
In
modern physical and mathematical research, the importance of
experience is also very notable. Chen Ning Yang once describes
great physicist Fermi’s basic research style: “We know that,
physics should not be a subject of experts, and physics should be
piled from the ground, laying one brick by another, and increasing
the height layer by layer. We know that, abstraction should be
after the concrete foundational work, and must never be before
it.”[33] While in
mathematical research, phenomenological theory is also very
important in the establishment process of general theory; in terms
of group theory, the reason why dihedral group is important is
because regular polyhedrons universally exist in nature, while the
reason for the importance of wave equation in partial differential
equation is also that wave phenomena appear in many natural
domains. Therefore, actual world’s experience provides the most
basic and most important materials for scientific research, and no
matter how abstract and complex the theories are, they should all
be built upon the solid foundation of many empirical facts, which
is a basic view many accomplished scientists all insist.
(III) The Relationship
between Human Society and Experience
In the
above, our comments on the value of philosophical epistemology in
scientific research are perhaps somewhat too harsh, when we turn
the analytical vision from scientific fields to social fields, what
we find out will be a very different overall picture, namely:
experience plays a central role in human society.
1 The use of mathematics in
economics. Since Marshall, economics starts
a grand trend of continuous mathematization; and from the latter
part of the 20th century, the process
of economics’ mathematization greatly accelerates, and economic
researches using mathematics as the basic tool become a common
practice and have gradually converged into the mainstream of
economics. The mathematization of economics can be roughly
inspected through two commonly used
textbooks-Sargent’s Recursive Macroeconomic
Theroy, and Varian’s Advanced
Microeconomics. It should be noted that, the
mathematization of economics definitely has a high value, like the
famous Solow model in development economics, which quantitatively
depicts the functions capital, labor and technology play in
economic development, and such kind of quantitative analysis has
certain advantages which qualitative analyses cannot compare with.
The mathematization of economics is not empty talk, and these
mathematical economical models all precisely characterize certain
economic behaviors in the actual domain, and take one fact the
financial circle is generally familiar with, Simons once is a
brilliant geometer, but he transfers from mathematics to finance
after 40, and founds Renaissance Technologies Corporation, working
in hedge funds field, and achieves huge success, and his
investments are exactly based upon mathematical models and computer
programming, thus, this example fully proves the explanatory power
of modern economics towards the real world. Nowdays, professions
like high-frequency trading based on mathematics are already widely
known.
But,
economics’ mathematization will possibly lead to another extreme,
namely, a blind worship for the scientific method, and this
excessively obsessed with science attitude often thinks that all
the economic behaviors can be precisely depicted by scientific
models, as Hayek says: “During the first half of the nineteenth
century a new attitude made its appearance. The term science came
more and more to be confined to the physical and biological
disciplines which at the same time began to claim for a special
rigorousness and certainty which distinguished them from others.
Their success was such that they soon came to exercise an
extraordinary fascination on those working in other fields, who
rapidly began to imitate their teaching and vocabulary. Thus the
tyranny commenced which the methods and techniques of the Sciences
in the narrow sense of the term have ever since exercised over the
other subjects. These became increasingly concerned to vindicate
their equal status by showing that their methods were the same as
those of their brilliantly successful sisters rather than by
adapting their methods more and more to their own particular
problems.”[34] People like
Comte are good representatives of this stream of thought, and Comte
thinks that he has found some universal truths which can be applied
everywhere in social fields, and his research method is also highly
similar to the method of natural sciences. Hayek is very concerned
about such kind of research paradigm of scientism, and he thinks
:“The conception of man deliberately building his civilization
stems from an erroneous intellectualism that regards human reason
as something standing outside nature and possessed of knowledge and
reasoning capacity independent of experience.”[35] He further
analyzes: “it is only natural that the scientists tend to stress
what we do know; but in the social field, where what we do not know
is often so much more important, the effect of this tendency may be
very misleading. Many of the Utopian constructions are worthless
because they follow the lead of theorists in assuming that we have
perfect knowledge.”[36] Namely, in
social fields, what we do not know is often much more than what we
know, thus, it is inevitably futile to construct an all-embracing
theoretical system through one people’s limited experience. As is
well known, the rationalist philosophy has led to many utopian
constructions in modern society, and these utopian constructions
often use the so-called scientization as the flag, and hold a
rational control view towards society, about this, Hayek
criticizes: “The scientistic as distinguished from the scientific
view is not an unprejudiced but a very prejudiced approach which,
before it has considered its subject, claims to know what is the
most appropriate way of investigating it.”[37] For Hayek’s
detailed expositions on this significant problem, please refer to
his relevant works, and through many significant conclusions found
by his lifelong persistent intellectual explorations, we should be
able to hold a profound, dialectic and balanced opinion about the
mathematization of certain subjects like economics and sociology;
we need to know that, many things in human society cannot be
integrated into neat and uniform theoretical models, and if we
blindly worship the scientific method, we will possibly lose many
most precious things in human society (like originality, individual
freedom, the strength of emotion, etc).
About this significant problem, famous
philosopher Putnam also holds the same basic view, and he writes:
“I argued in the previous lecture that although we do sometimes
succeed in constructing good explanatory models of some natural
kinds in physics, it is hopeless to seek an explanatory model of
the natural kind ‘human being’ (although we may, of course,
discover empirical regularities and perhaps even laws about human
beings). This is what accounts for the unformalizability of
practical knowledge.”[38] Namely,
Putnam also thinks that many human behaviors cannot be accurately
grasped by using scientific methods. Berlin also thinks alike:
“Social and political terms are necessarily vague. The attempt to
make the vocabulary of politics too precise may render it
useless.”[39]
2 The reason for the importance of experience in
economics. As common sense tells us,
experience plays a central role in economics, and the reason for
producing this basic phenomenon, well known economist Knight
thinks, is the enormous complexity of individual behaviours, and he
says: “The world is ‘really’ made up of units which not only do not
change (atoms, corpuscles, either, or what-not), but whose laws of
behaviour are simple and comprehensive. But it is contended that
there are so many of these units that the simple changes which they
undergo (ideally movements in space alone) give rise to a variety
of combinations which our
minds are unable to grasp in detail. We have examined this dogma
and been forced to the conclusion that whatever we find it pleasant
to assume for philosophical purposes, the logic of
our conduct assumes real
indeterminateness, real change, discontinuity.”[40] Namely, the
units of the world we live in are of large number, and their
permutations and combinations will result in endless complexity,
thus, these changes are impossible to completely describe by
mathematical models, and even they can be described, these models
are also unable to keep up with the pace of rapidly changing social
reality.
This
phenomenon Knight reveals has a deeper reason behind it, namely,
the extreme broadness of experience in human society; if we say
that there is trillions of information in scientific knowledge,
then, there is probably also trillions of information in life
experience of human society, and these huge amounts of information
is also fastly changing, and therefore, it is hard to imagine that
any mathematical model can describe such a complex large-scale
system. Thus, experience, as a means for human to qualitatively
understand the surrounding society, shows a high value, and
experience is extremely condensed equations and highly simplified
mathematical models, and these equations and mathematical models
which exist empirically are undoubtedly powerful tools for
individuals to understand the surrounding society, and they can
help us to better understand the surrounding world, and about this,
Whitehead once says: “our experience, dim and fragmentary as it is,
yet sounds the utmost depths of reality.”[41] Furthermore,
even in ancient society, life was also a continuous learning
process, while in modern society, the range of life experience is
ten times more than ancient society, thus, the accumulation of life
experience is more difficult and important. Montaigne also writes:
“Reason has so many forms that we know not to which to take;
experience has no fewer; the consequence we would draw from the
comparison of events is unsure, by reason they are always unlike.
There is no quality so universal in this image of things as
diversity and variety.” “Resemblance does not so much make one as
difference makes another. Nature has obliged herself to make
nothing other that was not unlike.” “Never did two men make the
same judgment of the same thing; and it’s impossible to find two
opinions exactly alike, not only in several men, but in the same
man, at diverse hours.”[42] What
Montaigne describes is naturally a universal and profound basic
phenomenon in individual life. To conclude, experience will
continue to play a central role in future human life, which is an
undoubtful basic fact.
Besides
experience has great broadness this evident feature, it also has
the basic feature of continuous variability, which also leads to
that experience plays a central role in human society. In modern
philosophy and modern social sciences, scholars often prefer things
with certainty, as Dewey says: “As a result, whatever in capable of
certainty is assumed to constitute ultimate Being, and everything
else is said to be merely phenomenal, or, in extreme cases,
illusory.” Dewey describes the universal mentality that
philosophers flee from the coarse and chaotic experience one after
another to hide in static and pleasant ordinary things: “Gross
experience is loaded with the tangled and complex; hence philosophy
hurries away from it to search out something so simple that the
mind can rest trustfully in it, knowing that it has no surprises in
store, that it will not spring anything to make trouble, that it
will stay put, having no potentialities in reserve.” Dewey further
points out: “The permanent enables us to rest, it gives peace; the
variable, the changing, is a constant challenge. Where things
change something is hanging over us. It is a threat of trouble.
Even when change is marked by hope of better things to come, that
hope tends to project its object as something to stay once for all
when it arrives.”[43] The
phenomenon Dewey describes naturally does not only fit
philosophers, and in real life, the social public also prefers
static and stable life, however, our surrounding world is always
turbulent, and diverse and chaotic experience is always in a fastly
changing process, and therefore, understanding the complex world we
live in by the means of experience has become an indispensible
basic work and living method.
The
importance of experience also embodies in the overall grasp of
social basic structure, and in the
classic Social Origins of Dictatorship and
Democracy, Moore writes: “By itself a quantitative measure of
social mobility tells us little about social anatomy and its
workings.” He then gives an example: “In the nineteenth-century
Prussia the members of the bourgeoisie who became connected with
the aristocracy generally absorbed the latter’s habbit and outlook.
Rather the opposite relationship held in England. Thus if we did
have a technically perfect measure of mobility that gave an
identical numerical reading for the amount of fusion in England and
Prussia, we would make a disastrous mistake in saying that the two
countries were alike on this score. Statistics are misleading traps
for the unwary reader when they abstract from the essence of the
situation the whole structural context in which social osmosis
takes place.”[44] This
important fact revealed by Moore through the above specific example
is certainly a good warning for the scholars excessively infatuated
with quantitative tools.
About the
high importance of experience in social fields, other scholars give
some other proof ideas, and when the well known scholar Berlin
elaborates Mill’s thoughts, he says: “He saw that men differed and
evolved, not merely as a result of natural causes, but also because
of what they themselves did to alter their own characters, at times
in unintended ways. This alone makes their conduct unpredictable,
and renders laws or theories, whether inspired by analogies with
mechanics or with biology, nevertheless incapable of embracing the
complexity and qualitative properties of even an individual
character, let alone a group of men.”[45] Namely, Mill
thinks that, not only human society’s external experience is very
broad and continuously changing, and thus, is difficult to model,
but also individual’s internal character and thoughts are also in a
constantly changing process, and thus, are also difficult to
precisely characterize by scientific method. Combining the complex
changes of both the external social experience and internal
individual character, we can naturally deepen the understanding
about experience’s basic value in human society.
3 The importance of experience in human
society. Besides experience’s fundamental
importance in economic behaviours and fundamental importance in
scientific research these two aspects, it also has some other basic
values in human society, and one of them is its value for human
perceptual world. In modern society, due to science and
technology’s enormous power embodied in practical areas, thus, it
often leads to a blind worship towards science, and about this
social atmosphere of over admiration about scientific knowledge,
Dewey once did profound reflections, and he wrote: “In the
assertion (implied here) that the great vice of philosophy is an
arbitrary ‘intellectualism’, there is no slight cast upon
intelligence and reason. By ‘intellectualism’ as an indictment is
meant the theory that all experiencing is a mold of knowing, and
that all subject-matter, all nature, is, in principle, to be
reduced and transformed till it is defined in terms identical with
the characteristics presented by refined objects of science as
such. The assumption of ‘intellectualism’ goes contrary to the
facts of what is primarily experienced. For things are objects to
be treated, used, acted upon and with, enjoyed and endured, even
more than things to be known.” Namely, Dewey thinks that, human
experience much more ingredients than those can be objectively
understood, and many factors in experience are necessarily unable
to be completely grasped by scientific cognition, while “all modes
of experiencing are ways in which some genuine traits of nature
come to manifest realization.”[46] Therefore,
the range of experience in human society is much broader than the
limited scientific experience.
About the
basic phenomenon pan scientism which exists universally in modern
society, Chang Hao also makes a similar description: “In the modern
world, science is fashionable, and people’s attitude towards
science often becomes idolatry, and scientific view then turns into
pan scientific view, and the so-called pan scientific view means an
attitude believing that the only credible knowledge for human is
science, and there is only one standard for science to determine
meaning and truth, namely, the check based on sensory experience.
This is certainly a very narrow opinion about human experience.
Because human experience, in fact, is very rich, and has many
levels and many aspects, but the pan scientific view insists that
we should not believe what cannot be confirmed by sensory
experience.”[47] Obviously,
this phenomenon Mr Chang characterizes and worries about is very
identical to the basic phenomenon Dewey describes.
About the
prevalence of pan scientific view, in The Birth
of Tragedy, Nietzsche also made severe
criticisms. In this aesthetic masterpiece, he criticizes the modern
culture in which people use a scientific attitude to treat life,
and he thinks that science’s thinking orientation is: “a man raised
above fear of death by knowledge and reason”, “reminding every
individual of his purpose, namely, to make existence intelligible
and thus apparently justified.” Namely, scientism believes that we
can solve all the life’s secrets through scientific exploration,
and Nietzsche further depicts: “how an unimaginable universal greed
for knowledge through the full extent of the educated world steered
knowledge around the high seas as the essential task for every
person of greater capabilities, a greed which it has been
impossible since then completely to expel from scientifc knowledge,
and how through this universal greed a common net of thinking was
cast over the entire earth for the first time (with even glimpses
of the rule-round workings of an entire solar system).” Therefore,
the ultimate effect by using a scientific attitude to treat life
is: “mechanism of ideas, judgments, and conclusions has been
valued, from Socrates on, as the highest activity and the most
admirable gift of nature, above all other faculties. Even the
noblest moral deeds, the sympathetic emotions, self-sacrifice,
heroism, and that calmness in the soul (so difficult to attain),
which the Apollonian Greeks called sophrosyne-all these were
derived by Socrates and his like-minded descendants right up to the
present from the dialectic of knowledge and therefore described as
teachable.”[48] To conclude,
in modern society, human’s various perceptual actions all need
rational explanations, and the modern psychology based upon physics
and physiology is a typical representative in them. While
Nietzsche’s basic view is : there are many things in life which
cannot be explained by science, and the most central one is the
death issue, and scientific knowledge cannot eliminate the gloomy
background cast over human society by death, and it will just
enable individuals to be indulged in superficial sensory enjoyment,
and evades the fundamental death issue. In Nietzsche’s view, the
meaning of life cannot be answered by science, and can only be
defused through art, and art has a central meaning in answering
many fundamental life issues. He thinks: “This is the true artistic
purpose of Apollo, in whose name we put together all those
countless illusions of beautiful appearances which render existence
at every moment in general worth living and push us to experience
the next moment.” “The Dionysian shows itself, measured against the
Apollonian, as the eternal and primordial artistic force, which
summons the entire world of appearances into existence.”[49] Namely,
Nietzsche hopes for the two basic factors Apollo and Dionysian in
art to solve the fundamental problem of the meaning of life.
Nietzsche’s thinking path here also deserves our
attention.
Besides
Nietzsche, Husserl also refutes the scientism, and he thinks that
knowledge about life is equally valuable as knowledge about the
objective world like mathematics and physics, and he writes: “The
universal transcendence in objective logical level-the universal
transcendence of mathematics and all the other transcendent
sciences in the usual sense-is founded on a kind of universal
transcendence prior to them, namely, the transcendence of pure
living world.”[50] Heidegger’s
opinions are also similar, and he says: “The human sciences, by
contrast, indeed all the sciences that deal with living things,
precisely in order to remain disciplined and rigorous, are
necessarily inexact. One can, indeed, view living things, too, as
magnitudes of spatio-temporal motion, but what one apprehends is
then no longer living. The inexactness of the historical human
sciences is not a deficiency but rather the fulfilment of an
essential requirement of this type of research.”[51]
Putnam also
thinks highly of the value of basic things like experience and
literature, and he says :“We can only understand the way in which
the literature imagination does really help us to understand
ourselves and life, on the other hand, and the way in which science
does really bear on metaphysical problems on the other, if we have
an adequate view of moral reasoning, where, by moral reasoning, I
mean not just reasoning about duty or virtue, but moral reasoning
in the widest sense-reasoning about how to live.”[52]
Max Weber’s
basic view on this central issue is also widely known, and he says
:“Who-aside from certain big children who are indeed found in the
natural sciences-still believes that the findings of astronomy,
biology, physics, or chemistry could teach us anything about the
meaning of the world? If there is any such ‘meaning’, along what
road could one come upon its tracks?”[53]
To conclude,
combining many thinkers’ clear expositions in the above and our
daily experience together, the enormous value of many beautiful
things like experience and art in human perceptual world is beyond
doubt. We should remember one basic truth : the barrenness of mind
is sometimes more dangerous than lack of knowledge, and barrenness
of mind will possibly lead the individual and society into the road
of destruction, and meanwhile, our mind can only be enriched and
infiltrated by non-scientific things like experience and art. Dewey
once makes a good summary about the importance of social knowledge:
“The successful maintenance of democratism strictly requires to use
the most efficient method to acquire social knowledge roughly
matching our substance knowledge, and invent and use the social
project roughly matching our technical ability about material
things.”[54] In
conclusion, experience has fundamental importance for keeping the
overall balance of human perceptual world and then for maintaining
human society’s richness and harmony.
4 The fundamental importance of experience in real
life. At the same time, the fundamental
importance of experience embodies most strongly and evidently in
people’s real life; it is easy to understand that, for many
individuals living in the real society, their practical lives
actualy do not need too much scientific knowledge, like policeman,
government official, lawyer, businessman and architectural worker;
for them, what they need most is systematic, flexible and delicate
life experience. As common sense tells us, most people in real life
will actually not passionately discuss and explore scientific
knowledge like scientists, and for them, scientific knowledge does
not have a core meaning, and what they think and face are mainly
many complex issues in work and life, and these issues include
clothing problem, traffic issue, household spending, job planning,
leisure and entertainment, etc, and they naturally all belong to
the category of living experience and work experience, and thus,
are all with a strong empirical color, and meanwhile, the range of
these life experience is very broad, and these living experience
are also hard to be strictly characterized by scientific knowledge,
therefore, experience is certainly more important than scientific
knowledge in real life. To sum up, considering that in most
people’s real life, life experience is so broad and so important,
while the importance of scientific knowledge is also not very
evident, therefore, the fundamental meaning of experience in actual
life naturally stands out.
In
conclusion, through the above expositions from several aspects, I
think we can somewhat well understand the multi-dimensional basic
values of experience in human society, and all of these
multi-dimensional values can naturally not be replaced by
scientific knowledge, and therefore, experience’s basic meaning in
human society is actually very profound, and also very
stable.
(IV) A Rethinking on the Relationship between Science and
Philosophy
It is easy to
see that, the comments on philosophical epistemology in part (II)
are somewhat negative, and through the relevant expositions in the
above part (III), about the meaning of philosophy this significant
theme, we should be able to hold a more sound view, and after the
investigations from both the positive and negative sides, here, it
is somewhat appropriate to overally evaluate the relationship
between philosophy and science.
In the era
before the 17th and
18th century, philosophy was often
regarded as the source of all sciences, and its status was above
concrete sciences, as Kant says: “she (metaphysics) was the queen
of all the sciences”[55] , but with
the enormous development of various scientific fields in the
19th and
20th century, philosophy’s this basic
positioning has been fundamentally challenged, and most
philosophers in the 20th century has
identified this basic fact, take Dewey for example, he writes:
“Since they admit that science is sovereign in the knowledge
domain, and this includes the entire territory of human experience.
This reduced approach excludes one kind of philosophy, and this
kind of philosophy thinks that philosophy is superior knowledge
than science, and it provides the knowledge about ultimate
high-level reality.” But, at the same time, Dewey thinks that
philosophy still has indispensbile basic values in modern society,
and about it, he says: “Excluding this special type of philosophy
does not mean that philosophy itself should be abandoned.” “As for
ordinary people, the reason why knowledge itself is important is
because it has influence over what he needs to do and what he wants
to create. It helps him to clarify his desires, helps him to form
his goal, and helps him to get the means of achieving these goals.
In other words, there are cognitive facts and principles, and there
are also values, and philosophy is basically studying values-it
studies the pursued goals of human action.”[56] Namely, Dewey
thinks that what philosophy cares about is the value domain, and it
can provide individual actions’ desires and goals, while these
things cannot be replaced by science, and meanwhile, these desires
and goals are also broad and complex, thus, philosophy still has
extensive and important values in human society. In conclusion,
since the 20th century, the
relationship between philosophy and science has appeared some basic
changes, and correspondingly, philosophy also needs to adjust its
basic positioning in human society.
In the
meantime, famous philosopher Whitehead’s thinking about this theme
also deserves our attention; firstly, he explains the basic
characteristics of science and philosophy: “The facts so far prove
that, in all the living things on earth, science and philosophy
only belong to mankind. Both of them emphasize to conceptualize
individual facts into the special cases of universal principles.
The principles are abstractly understood, while the facts are
understood as embodiments of the principles.” He further expounds:
“The term ‘curiosity’, in a larger sense (here we use it in this
way), means a kind of rational impulse, which hopes to understand
the facts separated from the experience, means a rejection of being
satisfied with messy facts, or a rejection of being satisfied with
pure normal habits. When people understand that every routine is a
special case to illustrate certain principle, and every principle
can be abstractly demonstrated through its many concrete cases,
then science and philosophy make the first step.” Namely, science
and philosophy are all devoted to abstracting individual facts into
universal general principles, and their differences are: “Science
emphasizes the observation about specific situations and induction
and generalization, and thereby, makes extensive classification
based on the mode of action of concrete things, in other words,
classifies them based on their natural law. While philosophy
emphasizes general propositions. Since the application range of
general propositions is too broad, and thus, they can hardly be
classified.” Namely, what philosophy emphasizes are general
propositions, while science must be based on concrete empirical
facts, and through this division, the value of philosophy then
shows up: “They (philosophical systems aimed at containing
everything) are methods for human spirit to foster its deeper
intuition. Through these systems, isolated ideas get vitality and
motion. If without these systems to coordinate, isolated ideas will
just accidentally emerge at any moment, and inspire thinking at
certain stage, and then wither and die and be forgotten by people.
The range of one kind of intuitive knowledge, can only be defined
by its coherent degree with many other universal concepts.”[57] Namely,
Whitehead thinks that, the value of philosophy is to universally
abstract and generalize many phenomena in human living world and
natural world, while the abstract conceptual system which
philosophy gets has deep and extensive subtle enlightenment towards
human life. Obviously, these analyses of Whitehead can also deepen
and broaden our basic understandings about the relationship between
science and philosophy.
In
conclusion, as two basic things in human society, philosophy and
science will both continuously develop with the progress of human
society, and their destinies will be necessarily intertwined with
human’s general destiny.
[1] The Discourse
On The Method, Part IV, p. 28, Oxford
University Press, 2006
[2] New Essays on
Human Understanding, Book I, Chapter I, p. 49, Commercial
Press, 1982
[3] We can refer to
Einstein’s comment on Mach’s philosophy: “Mach’s true greatness, is
his indestructible skepticism and independence.”
See Collected Essays of Albert
Einstein, Volume 1, “Self Narrative”, p. 10,
Commercial Press, 1976
[4] See Hao
Liuxiang’s paper “Weyl’s philosophical ideas and its relationship
with his mathematical and physical
research”, Scientific Culture Review, 2006,
3(5). This paper clearly combs the change process of Weyl’s
philosophical ideas.
[5] Like Russell’s
cumbersome but insubstantial discussions about “ truth” in Chapter
XV “ the definition of ‘truth’” of My
Philosophical Development
[6] About Yang’s
opinion about philosophy, we can refer to his some
statements:“Physics impacts philosophy, but philosophy has never
impacted physics.” “After quantum mechanics is established, it has
a large impact on philosophy, but when Heisenberg and Schrodinger
create quantum mechanics, they start from studying atomic spectra,
not from philosophy.” Mr. Yang’s attitudes to philosophy is
somewhat clear, namely, philosophy is not of much meaning to modern
physical research, and some famous physicists like Weinberg perhaps
also hold similar opinions, see the article “ On physical research
and teaching” in Collected Essays of Chen Ning
Yang, p. 514, East China Normal University
Press, 2000.
[7] Critique of
Pure Reason, Introduction, Part V, pp. 34, 35,
New York: Macmillan, 1922
[8] As early as the
age of E.T. Bell (1937), the mathematical world then already knew
the fallacy of Kant’s mathematical view, and Bell
writes: “Hamilton, who seems to have been
unacquainted with non-Euclidean geometry, followed Kant in
believing that ‘Time and space are two sources of knowledge from
which various a
priori synthetical cognitions can be derived.
Of this, pure mathematics gives a splendid example in the case of
our cognition of space and its various relations. As they are both
pure forms of sensuous intuition, they render synthetic
propositions a
priori possible.’ Of course any not utterly
illiterate mathematician today knows that Kant was mistaken in this
conception of mathematics, but in the 1840s, when Hamilton was on
his way to quaternions, the Kantian philosophy of mathematics still
made sense to those-and they were nearly all-who had never heard of
Lobatchewsky.” The basic view contained in Bell’s this description
is clear. See Men of Mathematics, Chapter
IXX, p. 394, Penguin Books, 1953.
[9] Critique of
Pure Reason, Part I, Chapter I, p. 45
[10] The quotations
of this passage are in Critique of Pure
Reason, Part I, Chapter I, pp. 45-47
[11] Li
Zehou: Critique of critical
philosophy, Chapter III, Section III, Renmin
Press, 1984. Li’s this work on Kant’s philosophy contains some
original ideas, but due to lack of necessary scientific training,
it get some false conclusions. For instance, he thinks that,
mathematics (like natural number, four arithmetic operations) stems
from human’s practical activities, and is related with human’s
subjectivity, which is naturally false, because mathematics is
obviously the basic structure of the universe itself.
[12] See The
History of Western Philosophy, Book III,
Chapter XX, pp. 715-716, Simon and Schuster, New York, 1945
[13] Critique of
Pure Reason, Part I, Section II, pp. 49-59
[14] See “What is
geometry”, included in Collected Essays of S.S.
Chern, pp. 267-273, East China Normal University, 2002
[15] Bull. London
Math Soc.34 (2002), 1-15
[16] See the paper
“The first physical synthesis” included
in Whitehead’s
Anthology, pp. 188-189, Zhejiang Art &
Literature Press, 1999
[17] See Collection
of Essays of Schopenhauer, Volume II, Chapter
IV, “The destiny of human life”, p. 189, Commercial Press, 2000
[18] Critique of
Pure Reason, Introduction, Section VI, p.
36
[19] We can refer to the famous physicist Feynman’s
attitude to science: “It is imperative in science
to doubt; it is absolutely necessary, for progress in science, to
have uncertainty as a fundamental part of your inner nature. To
make progress in understanding, we must remain modest and allow
that we do not know. Nothing is certain or proved beyond all doubt.
You investigate for curiosity, because it is unknown, not because
you know the answer.” See the paper “The relation of science and
religion” in The Pleasure of Finding Things
Out, pp. 247, 248, Perseus Books,
1999
[20] An Essay
Concerning Human Understanding, Book II,
Chapter VIII, pp. 100-101, Commercial Press, 1983
[21] See the paper
“The first physical synthesis” included
in Whitehead’s
Anthology, p. 183
[22] An Essay
Concerning Human Understanding, Book II,
Chapter I, p. 68
[23] New Essays on
Human Understanding, Preface, p. 3
[24] Critique of
Pure Reason, Part II, Introduction, Section I, pp. 64-65
[25] An Essay
Concerning Human Understanding, Book I, Chapter II, p. 6
[26] See the above
book, Book II, Chapter VI, p. 93
[27] See the article
“First meeting”, in Selection of Goethe’s
Proses, p. 217, Baihua Art & Literature
Press, 2005
[28] The
Principles of Psychology, Chapter II, Section
“sight”, p. 53, China City Press, 2003
[29] See the above
book, p. 53
[30] See the above
book, p. 65, interested readers can see the other parts of this
book
[31] Lakatos’
representative work Proofs and
Refutations centers on the well-known Euler’s
formula in topology, and its contents are very intricate, and this
book spreads widely.
[32] Experience
and Nature, Chapter I, pp. 1a-40, George Allen
& Unwin, Ltd, 1929
[33] See the article
“Professor Fermi” in Collected Essays of Chen
Ning Yang, p. 12, East China Normal University
Press, 2000
[34] The
Counter-Revolution of Science, Part I, Chapter
I, pp. 13-14, The Free Press, 1952
[35] The
Constitution of Liberty, Chapter II, p. 24,
The University of Chicago Press, 1978
[36] See the above
book, p. 23
[37] The
Counter-Revolution of Science, Part I, Chapter I, p. 16
[38] Meaning and
the Moral Sciences, Part I, Lecture IV
[39] See the essay
“Two concepts of liberty” in Liberty:
Incorporating Four Essays on Liberty, p. 204,
Oxford University Press, 2002
[40] Risk,
Uncertainty and Profit, Chapter XI, p. 161,
Houghton Mifflin, 1921
[41] Science and
the Modern World, Chapter I, p. 20, Pelican
Mentor Books, 1948
[42] “Of experience”,
see Essays of Montaigne, Volume 10
[43] Experience
and Nature, Chapter I
[44] Social
Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy, Chapter
I, Section IV, p. 37, Penguin University Books, 1973
[45] See the paper
“John Stuart Mill and the Ends of Life”, Section III,
in Liberty, p. 238
[46] Experience
and Nature, Chapter I, pp. 21-24, George Allen & Unwin,
Ltd, 1929
[47] See “Tradition
and modernization”, included in Gloomy
Consciousness and Democratic Tradition,p. 126, Xinxing Press,
2006
[48] The Birth of
Tragedy, Section XV, Dover Publications,
1995
[49] See the above
book, Section XXV. Nietzsche’s analyses about Apollo and Dionysian
these two art phenomena are very complex, and interested readers
can read this graceful and rich work, and the criticism towards
scientism and the admiration of art’s ontological value is
obviously one of the fundamental themes of this work by
Nietzsche.
[50] The Crisis of
European Sciences and Transcendental
Phenomenology, Section 37, p. 170, Commercial
Press, 2001
[51] See the
well-known paper “The age of the world picture”
in Off the Beaten Track, p. 60, Cambridge
University Press, 2002
[52] See Part II
“Literature, Science and Reflection” in Meaning
and the Moral Sciences. The central theme of this work by
Putnam is exactly to emphasize experience’s non-scientific property
and basic importance.
[53] See the
well-known essay “Science as a vocation”
[54] See the paper
“Democratic faith and education” in Problems of
Men, p. 23, Shanghai Renmin Press,
1986
[55] Critique of
Pure Reason, Preface to the first Edition
[56] See the essay
“The relationship between science and philosophy is the basis of
education” in Problems of Men
[57] Adventures of
Ideas, Chapter IX, “Science and philosophy”, The Free Press,
1967
加载中,请稍候......