标签:
杂谈 |
This dialectical way of doing moral reasoning goes
back to the ancients, to Plato and Aristotle, but it doesn't stop
with them, because there is a version of Socratic or dialectical
moral reasoning that is defended with great clarity and force by
John Rawls in giving an account of his method of justifying a
theory of justice. You remember it's not only the veil of ignorance
and the principles that Rawls argues for. It's also a method of
moral reasoning, reasoning about justice that he calls reflective
equilibrium.
What is the method of reflective equilibrium? It's
moving back and forth between our considered judgments about
particular cases and the general principles we would articulate to
make sense of those judgments. And not just stopping there, because
we might be wrong in our initial intuitions. Not stopping there but
then sometimes revising our particular judgments in the light of
the principles once we work them out. So sometimes we revise the
principles, sometimes we revise our judgments and intuitions in the
particular cases.
Now, there remains a further worry and it's a liberal worry, what about if we are going to think of our disagreements about morality and religion as bound up with our disagreements about justice, how are we ever going to find our way to a society that accords respect to fellow citizens with whom we disagree? It depends I think on which conception of respect one accepts. On the liberal conception, to respect our fellow citizens' moral and religious convictions, is, so to speak, to ignore them, for political purposes. To rise above or to abstract from or to set aside those moral and religious convictions. To leave them undisturbed, to carry on our political debate without reference to them. But that isn't the only way, or perhaps even the most plausible way of understanding the mutual respect on which democratic life depends. There is a different conception of respect according to which we respect our fellow citizens' moral and religious convictions, not by ignoring, but by engaging them. By attending to them. Sometimes by challenging and contesting them. Sometimes by listening and learning from them. Now, there's no guarantee that a politics of moral and religious attention and engagement will lead in any given case to agreement. There is no guarantee it will lead even to appreciation for the moral and religious convictions of others.It's always possible, after all, that learning more about a religious or a moral doctrine will lead us to like it less. But the respect of deliberation and engagement seems to me a more adequate, more suitable ideal for a pluralist society. And to the extent that our moral and religious disagreements reflect some ultimate plurality of human goods. A politics of moral engagement will better enable us, so it seems to me, to appreciate the distinctive goods our different lives expressed.
When we first came together some 13 weeks ago, I
spoke of the exhilaration of political philosophy and also of its
dangers. About how philosophy works and has always worked by
estranging us from the familiar by unsettling our settled
assumptions. And I tried to warn you that once the familiar turns
strange, once we begin to reflect on our circumstance, it's never
quite the same again. I hope you have by now experienced at least a
little of this unease because this is the tension that animates
critical reflection and political improvement and maybe even the
moral life as well.
And so our argument comes to an end, in a sense, but
in another sense goes on. Why, we asked at the outset, why did
these arguments keep going even if they raise questions that are
impossible ever, finally, to resolve? The reason is that we live
some answer to these questions all the time. In our public life,
and in our personal lives, philosophy is inescapable even if it
sometimes seems impossible. We began with the thought of Kant, that
skepticism is a resting place for human reason. Where it can
reflect upon its dogmatic wanderings, but it is no dwelling place
for permanent settlement. To allow ourselves simply to acquiescence
in skepticism or in complacence, Kant wrote, can never suffice to
overcome the restlessness of reason.
The aim of this course has been to awaken the restlessness of reason and to see where it might lead. And if we had done at least that, and if the restlessness continues to afflict you in the days and years to come, then we together have achieved no small thing.
Thank you.