MathematicalBackground:FoundationsofInnitesimalCalculussecondedition
(2019-06-20 12:33:00)Mathematical Background: Foundations of Innitesimal Calculus second edition
by
K. D. Stroyan
x
y
y=f(x)
dx
dy
δx
ε
dx
dy
Figure 0.1: A Microscopic View of the Tangent
Copyright c
1997 by Academic Press, Inc. - All rights reserved.
Typeset with AMS-TEX
i
Preface to the Mathematical Background
We want you to reason with
mathematics. We are not trying to get everyone to give formalized
proofs in the sense of contemporary mathematics; ‘proof’ in this
course means ‘convincing argument.’ We expect you to use correct
reasoning and to give careful explanations. The projects bring out
these issues in the way we nd best for most students, but the pure
mathematical questions also interest some students. This book of
mathematical “background” shows how to ll in the mathematical
details of the main topics from the course. These proofs are
completely rigorous in the sense of modern mathematics –
technically bulletproof. We wrote this book of foundations in part
to provide a convenient reference for a student who might like to
see the “theorem - proof” approach to calculus. We alsowroteit for
the interestedinstructor. In re-thinking the presentationof
beginning calculus, we found that a simpler basis for the theory
was both possible and desirable. The pointwise approach most books
give to the theory of derivatives spoils the subject. Clear simple
argumentslike the proofof the FundamentalTheoremat the startof
Chapter 5 below are not possible in that approach. The result of
the pointwise approach is that instructors feeltheyhaveto either
bedishonestwithstudents ordisclaimgoodintuitivea
ii
derivatives, although this can also
be clearly understood using function limits as in the text by Lax,
et al, from the 1970s. Modern graphical computing can also help us
“see” graphs convergeas stressed in our main materials and in the
interesting Uhl, Porta, Davis, Calculus & Mathematica text.
Almost all the theorems in this book are well-known old results of
a carefully studied subject. The well-known ones are more important
than the few novel aspects of the book. However, some details like
the converseof Taylor’s theorem – both continuous and discrete –
arenotsoeasytondintradit
Contents
Part 1 Numbers and Functions Chapter 1. Numbers 3 1.1 Field Axioms 3 1.2 Order Axioms 6 1.3 The Completeness Axiom 7 1.4 Small, Medium and Large Numbers 9 Chapter 2. Functional Identities 17 2.1 Specic Functional Identities 17 2.2 General Functional Identities 18 2.3 The Function Extension Axiom 21 2.4 Additive Functions 24 2.5 The Motion of a Pendulum 26 Part 2 Limits Chapter 3. The Theory of Limits 31 3.1 Plain Limits 32 3.2 Function Limits 34 3.3 Computation of Limits 37 Chapter 4. Continuous Functions 43 4.1 Uniform Continuity 43 4.2 The Extreme Value Theorem 44
iii
iv Contents
4.3 Bolzano’s Intermediate Value Theorem 46 Part 3 1 Variable Dierentiation Chapter 5. The Theory of Derivatives 49 5.1 The Fundamental Theorem: Part 1 49 5.1.1 Rigorous Innitesimal Justication 52 5.1.2 Rigorous Limit Justication 53 5.2 Derivatives, Epsilons and Deltas 53 5.3 Smoothness ⇒ Continuity of Function and Derivative 54 5.4 Rules ⇒ Smoothness 56 5.5 The Increment and Increasing 57 5.6 Inverse Functions and Derivatives 58 Chapter 6. Pointwise Derivatives 69 6.1 Pointwise Limits 69 6.2 Pointwise Derivatives 72 6.3 Pointwise Derivatives Aren’t Enough for Inverses 76 Chapter 7. The Mean Value Theorem 79 7.1 The Mean Value Theorem 79 7.2 Darboux’s Theorem 83 7.3 Continuous Pointwise Derivatives are Uniform 85 Chapter 8. Higher Order Derivatives 87 8.1 Taylor’s Formula and Bending 87 8.2 Symmetric Dierences and Taylor’s Formula 89 8.3 Approximation of Second Derivatives 91 8.4 The General Taylor Small Oh Formula 92 8.4.1 The Converse of Taylor’s Theorem 95 8.5 Direct Interpretation of Higher Order Derivatives 98 8.5.1 Basic Theory of Interpolation 99 8.5.2 Interpolation where f is Smooth 101 8.5.3 Smoothness From Dierences 102 Part 4 Integration Chapter 9. Basic Theory of the Denite Integral 109 9.1 Existence of the Integral 110
Contents v
9.2 You Can’t Always Integrate Discontinuous Functions 114 9.3 Fundamental Theorem: Part 2 116 9.4 Improper Integrals 119 9.4.1 Comparison of Improper Integrals 121 9.4.2 A Finite Funnel with Innite Area? 123 Part 5 Multivariable Dierentiation Chapter 10. Derivatives of Multivariable Functions 127 Part 6 Dierential Equations Chapter 11. Theory of Initial Value Problems 131 11.1 Existence and Uniqueness of Solutions 131 11.2 Local Linearization of Dynamical Systems 135 11.3 Attraction and Repulsion 141 11.4 Stable Limit Cycles 143 Part 7 Innite Series Chapter 12. The Theory of Power Series 147 12.1 Uniformly Convergent Series 149 12.2 Robinson’s Sequential Lemma 151 12.3 Integration of Series 152 12.4 Radius of Convergence 154 12.5 Calculus of Power Series 156 Chapter 13. The Theory of Fourier Series 159 13.1 Computation of Fourier Series 160 13.2 Convergence for Piecewise Smooth Functions 167 13.3 Uniform Convergence for Continuous Piecewise Smooth Functions 173 13.4 Integration of Fourier Series 175
-4 -2 2 4
w
-4
-2
2
4
x
Part 1
Numbers and Functions
2
CHAPTER 1 Numbers This chapter gives the algebraic laws of the number systems used in calculus.
Numbers represent various idealized measurements. Positive integers may count items, fractions may represent a part of an item or a distance that is part of a xed unit. Distance measurements go beyond rational numbers as soon as we consider the hypotenuse of a right triangle or the circumference of a circle. This extension is already in the realm of imagined “perfect” measurements because it corresponds to a perfectly straight-sided triangle with perfect rightangle, or a perfectly round circle. Actual realmeasurements arealwaysrational and have some error or uncertainty. The various “imaginary” aspects of numbers are very useful ctions. The rules of computation with perfect numbers are much simpler than with the error-containing real measurements. This simplicity makes fundamental ideas clearer. Hyperreal numbers have ‘teeny tiny numbers’ that will simplify approximationestimates. Direct computations with the ideal numbers produce symbolic approximations equivalent to the function limits needed in dierentiation theory (that the rules of Theorem 1.12 give a direct way to compute.) Limit theory does not give the answer, but only a way to justify it once you have found it.
1.1 Field Axioms
The laws of algebra follow from the eld axioms. This means that algebra is the same with Dedekind’s “real” numbers, the complex numbers, and Robinson’s “hyperreal” numbers.
3
4 1. Numbers
Axiom 1.1. Field Axioms A “eld” of numbers is any set of objects together with two operations, addition and multiplication where the operations satisfy: • The commutative laws of addition and multiplication, a1 + a2 = a2 + a1 & a1 ·a2 = a2 ·a1 • The associative laws of addition and multiplication, a1 +(a2+a3)=(a1+a2)+a3 & a1·(a2·a3)=(a1·a2)·a3 •The distributive law of multiplication over addition, a1 ·(a2 + a3)=a1·a2+a1·a3 •There is an additive identity, 0, with0+a=afor every number a. • There is an multiplicative identity, 1, with1·a=afor every number a 6=0. •Each number a has an additive inverse, −a, witha+(−a)=0. •Each nonzero number a has a multiplicative inverse, 1 a, witha·1 a=1. A computation needed in calculus is Example 1.1. The Cube of a Binomial
(x +x)3 =x3+3x2x+3xx2+x3 =x3+3x2x+(x(3x +x))x
We analyze the term ε = (x(3x
+x)) in dierentiation.
Thereadercouldlaboriousl
(x+x)3 =(x+x)(x +x)(x +x) =(x+x)((x +x)(x +x)) =(x+x)((x +x)x+(x+x)x) =(x+x)((x2 + xx)+(xx+x2)) =(x+x)(x2 + xx + xx +x2) =(x+x)(x2 +2xx+x2) =(x+x)x2+(x+x)2xx +(x+x)x2) . . .
The natural counting numbers 1,2,3,...have operations of addition and multiplication, but do not satisfy all the properties needed to be a eld. Addition and multiplication do satisfy the commutative, associative, and distributive laws, but there is no additive inverse
Field Axioms 5
0 in the counting numbers. In
ancient times, it was controversial to add this element that could
stand for counting nothing, but it is a useful ction in many kinds
of computations. The negative integers −1,−2,−3,...are another
idealization added to the natural numbers that make additive
inverses possible - they are just new numbers with the needed
property. Negative integers have perfectly concrete interpretations
such as measurements to the left, rather than the right, or amounts
owed rather than earned. The set of all integers; positive,
negative, and zero, still do not form a eld because there are no
multiplicative inverses. Fractions,±1/2,±1/3, ...are the needed
additional inverses. When they are combined with the integers
through addition, we have the set of all rational numbers of the
form ±p/q for natural numbers p and q 6= 0. The rational numbers
are a eld, that is, they satisfy all the axioms above. In ancient
times, rationals were sometimes considered only “operators” on
“actual” numbers like 1,2,3,.... The point of the previous
paragraphs is simply that we often extend one kind of number system
in order to have a new system with useful properties. The complex
numbers extend the eld axioms above beyond the “real” numbers by
adding a number i that solves the equation x2 = −1. (See the CD
Chapter 29 of the main text.) Hundreds of years ago this number was
controversial and is still called “imaginary.” In fact, all numbers
are useful constructs of our imagination and some aspects of
Dedekind’s “real” numbers are much more abstract than i2 = −1. (For
example, since the reals are “uncountable,” “most” real numbers
have no description what-so-ever.) The rationals are not “complete”
in the sense that the linear measurement of the side of an
equilateral right triangle (√2) cannot be expressed as p/q
for p and q integers. In Section 1.3 we “complete”
the
rationals to form Dedekind’s “real”
numbers.
These numbers correspond to perfect measurements along an ideal
line with no gaps. The complex numbers cannot be ordered with a
notion of “smaller than” that is compatible with the eld
operations. Adding an “ideal” number to serve as the square root
of−1 is not compatible with the square of every number being
positive. When we make extensions beyond the real number system we
need to make choices of the kind of extension depending on the
properties we want to preserve. Hyperreal numbers allow us to
compute estimates or limits directly, rather than making inverse
proofs with inequalities. Like the complex extension, hyperreal
extension of the reals loses a property; in this case completeness.
Hyperreal numbers are explained beginning in Section 1.4 below and
then are used extensively in this background book to show how many
intuitive estimates lead to simple direct proofs of important ideas
in calculus. The hyperreal numbers (discovered by Abraham Robinson
in 1961) are still controversial because they contain
innitesimals. However, they are just another extended modern
number system with a desirable new property. Hyperreal numbers can
help you understand limits of real numbers and many aspects of
calculus. Results of calculus could be proved without
innitesimals, just as they could be proved without real numbers by
using only rationals. Many professors still prefer the former, but
few prefer the latter. We believe that is only because Dedekind’s
“real” numbers are more familiar than Robinson’s, but we will make
it clear how both approaches work as a theoretical background for
calculus. There is no controversy concerning the logical soundness
of hyperreal numbers. The use ofinnitesimals inthe
earlydevelopmentofcalcul
6 1. Numbers
With hindsight, they also have a simple description. The Function Extension Axiom 2.1 explained in detail in Chapter 2 was the missing key.
Exercise set 1.1 1. Show that the identity numbers 0 and 1 are unique. (HINT: Suppose 00 + a = a. Add −ato both sides.) 2. Show that 0·a =0. (HINT: Expand0+b a·awith the distributive law and show that0 ·a+b = b. Then use the previous exercise.) 3. The inverses −a and 1 a are unique. (HINT: Suppose not, 0=a−a=a+b. Add−a to both sides and use the associative property.) 4. Show that −1·a =−a. (HINT: Use the distributive property on 0 = (1−1)·a and use the uniqueness of the inverse.) 5. Show that (−1)·(−1) = 1. 6. Other familiar properties of algebra follow from the axioms, for example, if a3 6=0and a4 6=0, then a 1+a 2 a 3 =a 1 a 3 +a 2 a 3 , a 1·a 2 a 3·a 4 =a 1 a 3· a 2 a 4 & a 3·a 46=0
1.2 Order Axioms Estimation is based on the inequality ≤ of the real numbers.
Oneimportantrepresentati